Skip to main content

Full text of "Ideas of order in seventeenth-century music writing"

See other formats


IDEAS OF ORDER IN SEVENTEENTH-CENTURY MUSIC WRITING 

Melanie K. Brooks-Nelson 
B.A., University of Illinois, 1977 



A thesis submitted to the 

University of Colorado Denver 

in partial fulfillment 

of the requirements for the degree of 

Master of Arts 

History 

2012 



© 2012 by Melanie K. Brooks-Nelson 
All rights reserved 



This thesis for the Master of Arts Degree by 

Melanie K. Brooks-Nelson 

has been approved for the 

Master of Arts in History 

by 



Carl Pletsch, Chair 

Carl Pletsch, Advisor 

Richard Smith 

Gabriel Finkelstein 



April 8, 2012 



Brooks-Nelson, Melanie K. (M.A., History) 

Ideas of Order in 17 l -Century Music Writing 

Thesis directed by Professor Carl Pletsch 

ABSTRACT 

England in the seventeenth century was in the midst of turmoil: political, religious, 
and scientific. Civil war and regicide, puritan dissension, and a fundamental shift in 
the perception of nature all challenged the presumption of unity encoded in the notion 
of the harmony of the spheres. The very foundation of order and authority was at 
stake; but because the presumption of unity had prevented the development of a 
language of diversity, the historian has few sources for the transparent expression of 
conflict to mine for cultural meaning. The arts though are rich, albeit less than 
transparent, sources for investigating conflict; and because the harmony of the 
spheres was more than mere metaphor but perceived to be the very structure of the 
cosmos, seventeenth-century musical writing especially, both by well-known natural 
philosophers and by lesser-known musical theorists, encodes shifting notions of 
authority and order. These writers both created new musical theory and disputed 
theoretical issues, especially that of temperament tuning: the necessity to modify the 
heretofore perfect Pythagorean intervals to accommodate modern musical instruments 
and polyphony. In challenging the perfection of Pythagorean intervals and in claiming 
musical theory to be the provenance of human creation rather than of nature, musical 
writers were prognosticators unaware, trumpeting the shift to modernity as humanity 
wrested control of its destiny from the cosmos. 



This abstract accurately represents the content of the candidate's thesis. I recommend 
its publication. 

Carl Pletsch 



ACKNOWLEDGEMENT 

I wish to thank my advisor, Carl Pletsch, for insights that guided me to core issues in 
my research. 



TABLE OF CONTENTS 
CHAPTER 

1. INTRODUCTION 1 

2. CHANGING BELIEFS ABOUT NATURE AND MUSIC 10 

The Tuning Conundrum 11 

Music's Place in Philosophy 13 

Four Early Philosophers on Music 16 

3. MUSIC AND THE NEW PHILOSOPHY 20 

Three Natural Philosophers on Music 21 

Bacon 21 

Hooke 31 

Newton 36 

4. HUMANITY CREATING ITS OWN MEANING 39 

Music Central to That Change 41 

Changing Ideas of Nature in Music Writing 42 

5. THE NEW PHILOSOPHY: MUSIC AS SOURCE OF ORDER 59 

Acknowledging Diversity with Loss of Celestial Harmony 63 

Continuing Religiosity With Philosophical Changes 65 

6. CONCLUSION 76 

WORKS CITED 80 



CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION 

In the late sixteenth century, the Rosicrucian scholar Robert Fludd 
diagrammed a Christianized concept of the Pythagorean monochord, the harmony of 
the world in pictorial detail, displaying the musical order imposed by God — a 
speculative, all-encompassing cosmological scheme. Calling it the Divine 
Monochord, his detailed chart consists of two octaves, with internal intervals 
designating hierarchical elements of the universe: earth, God, highest heaven. 
"Totally synthesizing macro- and microcosm was Fludd' s sensible and ambitious goal 
in life." 1 But his intricately constructed scheme amounted to the vain attempt of one 
man to "put together again the Humpty Dumpty fragments of science, philosophy, 
and religion," which by then, on the cusp of the seventeenth century, had been 
"irrevocably sundered." Fludd' s was the final great "flowering of speculative 

• >»3 

music. 

It was the Renaissance and it was modernity: divine right of kings and self- 
governance; natural magic and natural philosophy; harmony of the spheres and the 
silencing of the harmony; the great chain of being and the taxonomy of nature; Truth 
and facts; man's place within a holistically organic nature and man's manipulation of 
nature; music of numbers and music of sound; Pythagorean perfect intervals and 



Anthony Aveni, Behind the Crystal Ball: Magic, Science, and the Occult from Antiquity Through the 
New Age (New York: Times Books, 1996), 81. 

Jamie James, The Music of the Spheres: Music, Science, and the Natural Order of the Universe (New 
York: Copernicus, 1993), 128. 

Joscelyn Godwin, Music, Mysticism, and Magic: A Science Book (London, New York: Routledge and 
Kegan Paul, 1986), 143. 



tempered tuning. Whatever one calls the transformation during the long seventeenth 
century — the Scientific Revolution writ large or small — England at the end of the 
century was a world fundamentally changed from the England of the later sixteenth 
century. The transformation, though, far from being linear or cumulative, was marked 
rather by shifting and shared intellectual spaces, conflict and conflation, recession and 
ascendance, anomaly and concordance. The philosophical debates that so consumed 
thinkers and writers early on were left behind by the end of the period, not so much 
resolved as peripheralized. The century was witness to an epistemological shift none 
could have foreseen. The intellectual upheaval was defined by changing and 
diversifying sources of authority in natural philosophy, politics, and religion. By the 
end of the century, the notion of a harmonious cosmos had lost both its intellectual 
bite and its cultural meaning as a shared perception of reality. 

The first Stuart king of England, James I (James VI of Scotland), ruling after 
Elizabeth from 1603-1625, continued her priority, formalized in the Elizabethan 
Settlement, of maintaining harmony and a vision of unity within society, the via 
media, treading a moderate path that rejected extremism in religion and politics and 
elevated civil peace as the supreme good. The beginnings of a fundamental 
breakdown in this harmonious perception of reality were evident in religion and 
politics; and natural philosophers were already experimenting and exploring beyond 
Renaissance frames of reference, rethinking assumptions about nature and the 
cosmos. But both Elizabeth and James, through sheer force of powerful personae and 



Mister McGrath, In the Beginning: The Story of the King James Bible and How It Changed a Nation, 
and Language, and a Culture (New York, London, Toronto, Sydney, Auckland: Doubleday, 2001), 160. 



ability to cajole, persuade, appease, and manipulate, were able to maintain the 
appearance of unity and harmony, even as its breakdown was increasingly manifest in 
natural philosophy, religion, and politics. 

The rule of Charles I beginning in 1625 was not marked by the political ability 
or force of personality of Elizabeth and James; he lacked the gifts to contain the 
increasing fragmentation evident in society. His constant plying Parliament for more 
funds, taking a Catholic bride, and choosing an archbishop widely perceived to be 
much too cozy with Rome all served to raise the alarm of the people about the 
maintenance of order. Where James had been able to placate and sustain the status 
quo, Charles angered and, fatally, lost the trust of the people to rule for the common 
good and to maintain order. The fall of the monarchy, regicide, and the interregnum 
Commonwealth, far from being assaults on order, were attempts to restore order 
within a society whose fear of chaos ranked almost equally with fear of eternal 
damnation. Far from a clarion call for democracy, the condemnation of Charles and 
turn to Parliament represented a desperate pursuit of an alternative source of unity 
and order as monarchial disorder ran amok. 

But unity, real or perceived, was never again to be. The mid-century break of 
the Civil War and Commonwealth was more than political, more even than religious. 
A changed society emerged from the grist of that mill, shocked at what had been 
wrought in the beheading of a king, but never again to wholly trust king or 
Parliament; agonizingly anxious to restore order and enforce civil conformity, but 



5 McGrath, In the Beginning, 289. 



forced to recognize fragmentation of authority in religion, politics, and natural 
philosophy. The Restoration of the monarchy was not a return to former times, but a 
new tacit agreement between people and king that the latter must accommodate the 
former in new ways; William and Mary sailing into London in the Glorious 
Revolution of 1688 made manifest the changed relationship between the people and 
the monarchy. 

That changed relationship was symptomatic of a shift throughout society, not 
announced or articulated, and certainly not appreciated for the profound social and 
cultural change it represented — nuanced and subtle — yet utterly transformational. 
Even as that shift permeated society, it entered into artistic products, representations 
of shared cultural meanings. Art as ideological statement, that is, addressing notions 
of order and authority, illuminates the changed epistemology from one of a unitary, 
harmonious source of cosmological order expressed in the great chain of being and 
the universal monochord to the recognition of diverse sources of authority; from the 
notion of absolute Truth to acceptance of good-enough standards of truth; from God 
as immanent in an organic, holistic nature to God the Creator existing outside His 
Creation, a nature to be experimented on and manipulated by man. 

Just as fundamental changes in natural philosophy were part of the 
fragmentation of order and authority in politics and religion, so changing ideas about 
the role of music in the cosmos and about basic assumptions in music theory were 
embedded in the changing notions about nature and natural philosophy. Music was 
identified with the harmony and order that structured all of society, an identification 



that broke down as the reality of that harmonious unity in society broke apart and 
music bifurcated into science and art, no longer the metaphysical glue of the cosmos. 
Monumental as was the shift in music's role, it yet crept in like a thief in the night, 
neither noticed nor noted, predicted nor understood, like the unheralded entrance of 
the general epistemological shift of the century. No one willed what happened or 
directed its occurrence; but by the end of the century, natural philosophy had become 
merely science, and humanity bore the full weight of responsibility for the creation of 
order and meaning in a cosmos devoid of both. 

The central role of music in the shift to experimental science in the 
seventeenth century it has been scantily studied in this connection. Historians of 
music concentrate on the history of method and performance practice, largely 
irrespective of complex intellectual connections and currents of the century; and 
historians of science have consigned music to the art category and thus not within 
their purview. More broadly, music in relation to natural philosophy has not been 
duly investigated. Historians have largely ignored the centrality of music in 

o 

"structuring. . .knowledge and reality," an omission of the intellectual map of that 
century. 



Penelope Gouk, Music, Science, and Natural Magic in Seventeenth-Century England (New Haven and 
London: Yale University Press, 1999), 19. 

Jamie Kassler, The Beginning of the Modern Philosophy of Music in England (Aldershot, Hampshire, 
England and Burlington, Vermont: Ashgate, 2004), 2; Linda Phyllis Austern, "'Tis Nature's Voice: 
music, natural philosophy, and the hidden world in seventeenth-century England," in Music Theory 
and Natural Order From the Renaissance to the Early Twentieth Century, eds. Suzanne Clark and 
Alexander Rending (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), 31. 

Paolo Gozza, ed., Preface, Number to Sound: The Musical Way to the Scientific Revolution 
(Dordrecht, Boston, London: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2000), xii. 



Music writing of the seventeenth century is an integral part of cultural history 
as a rich source of ideological statement in a matrix joining reality, representation, 
and perception. Culture is implicit in constructing reality; cultural representations 
"embody and signify political codes and values," 1 that is, notions of order and the 
control of disorder. Musical writing is an important piece within the wide range of 
cultural practices of the seventeenth century in addressing ideas of order; 
investigating it helps redress its virtual omission in the century's cultural topography. 

About 100 treatises were produced in England in the long seventeenth century 
(1580-1720), more than in any other place. 11 Investigating these and other musical 
writing is a sort of discourse analysis to reveal ideological meanings within cultural 
practices, a way to examine questions of authority through these cultural 
representations. These not only reflect prevailing ideas of order and authority, but 
also inform and shape attitudes and beliefs: cultural discourse as ideological 
legitimacy and context for political statement. This "cultural turn" in historical study 
helps to avoid the pitfalls of imposed meanings, categories, and dichotomies in favor 
of listening to contemporary sources' own ideas of order and authority as expressed 
through cultural products, an additional way to read the tumultuous events of the 
seventeenth century. 



Sharpe, Kevin, Remapping Early Modern England. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000, 15. 
Clifford Geertz, quoted in Sharpe, Remapping, 17. 

Rebecca Herisonne, Music Theory in Seventeenth-Century England. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 
2000, 6; Austern, "'Tis Nature's Voice," 31. 
Sharpe, Remapping, 18-19. 



Taking this cultural turn in intellectual history by reading musical writing has 
resonance on another level for the seventeenth century. Musical writing as a cultural 
expression has to do with order, not only in the general sense as in any historical 
context; it also directly relates to the commonweal of the seventeenth century because 
of a continuing and pervasive belief in correspondences and analogies through most 
of the seventeenth century. These normatively depicted the cosmos as an 
interconnected hierarchy — a representation, not a metaphor — and writers of the time 
were clear about the distinction. Truth on one level of meaning translated to truth in 
another; this system of analogies was widely accepted and virtually unquestioned. 13 
Music was identified with order through the harmony of the spheres and the universal 
monochord. Order was the very fabric of the universe, expressed and organized by 
music; 1 and the tortuous route of the lost intellectual cache of this pervasive belief is 
a critical piece of seventeenth-century intellectual history. 

As part of its being a cultural representation of ideas of order and authority, 
music occupies the same intellectual space as natural philosophy in the seventeenth 
century, the former expressing identical notions of order and disorder, attitudes 
toward nature and sources of authority as the latter. England was thrown into 
epistemological ferment after papal authority was dethroned; writing about music is 
one way to view the ensuing intellectual debates, political, religious, and 



Sharpe, Remapping, 44. 
James, Music of the Spheres, 3. 



philosophical. 5 The same network of practitioners of natural philosophy also wrote 
about music in a speculative mode; that is, although they occasionally addressed 
issues in musical theory, including the vexing one of tuning, they wrote more broadly 
about the underlying mathematical and physical principles of music, beginning with 
that iconic advocate of the experimental philosophy, Francis Bacon, and including 
Hooke and Newton. 1 Still, historians have been slow to appreciate the importance of 
musical models. 

Musical treatise writers in England, who seemed nearly obsessed with order in 
their construction of a complex edifice of musical theory, incorporated the new 
thinking about nature and order in their writing. Musical writing, like the New 
Science in the seventeenth century, acted as a kind of code for imposing order; but the 
code creators themselves were unaware of their role in the changing epistemology. To 
this end, then, musical theorists both participated in and perpetuated new ways of 
thinking of nature and music, even as they unselfconsciously continued alluding to 
earlier Pythagorean musical notions of order and authority. Those writing about 
music debated the urgent problem of tuning — division of the scale, consonances, and 
the proper nature of intervals — as well as more trivial ones: whether or not to attach 
syllable names, in addition to letter names, to the notes of the scale; the optimal 
number of lines on a staff; which note to assign to the bottom line of the staff. The 
musical theory emerged in the context and as a reflection of epistemological change; 



Ann Geneva, Astrology and the Seventeenth Century Mind: William Lilly and the Language of the 
Stars (Manchester, New York: Manchester University Press, 1995), 40. She uses astrology as a similar 
mapping device for the debates of that century. 

Gouk, Music, Science, 3, 25. 



so musical texts were sites of philosophical debate, albeit unconscious and non- 
transparent. 

The distinction between natural philosophers using musical models and 
musical theorists writing about music, though, is a difference of intent. Both 
addressed, in varying texts, changing ideas of music and music theory that were an 
integral part of the more general intellectual ferment in natural philosophy. 
Intellectual sites, then, for the new musical theory being threshed out were the same 
ones as for the new experimental philosophy, embedded in changing notions of nature 
and of sources of authority; and all musical writing of the seventeenth century, 
experimental to practical, constitutes a single body of musical discourse mapping the 
intellectual upheaval of the century. That the upheaval resulted in a foundational 
philosophical shift by the end of the century was entirely an unintended consequence. 



CHAPTER 2. CHANGING BELIEFS ABOUT NATURE AND MUSIC 

These writers addressed not only the tuning problem but a range of issues 
relating to music theory, creating most of the musical theory structure in place today. 
Beliefs about nature inform music, always; and ideas about the natural order, though 
having the gloss of immutability, are culturally determined. Music writing throughout 
history attests to both its role as agent of change and its susceptibility to be changed 

1 7 

by culture. As ideas about nature change, so do ideas about music. Nature imposes 
order on music theory, legitimizing it and providing authority for rules that, because 
seemingly based on nature, appear to transcend culture and history. This illusion is 
particularly salient for the shift from absolute Truth to scientific truth, "reliable rather 
than certain knowledge," in the seventeenth century. Even though truth was no 
longer certain, the metaphysical search for it just did not matter anymore; reasonable 
standards of truth about observable nature held sway. Importantly, though, as the new 
natural philosophy narrowed into experimental science, abandoning any claim to 
absolute Truth, it still retained its claim to universality, thus establishing its 
hegemonic claim to knowledge in the modern era, "epistemologically privileged 
discourse." 

Just so, music morphed from a cosmological, mysterious, metaphysical 
construct to a pursuit accessible and susceptible to scientific inquiry. Music was 



Gozza, Introduction, Number to Sound, 29. 

Clark and Rending, Introduction, Music Theory, 2. 

Karl Popper, quoted in Clark and Rending, Music Theory, fn 5, 2. 

Clark and Rending, Introduction, Music Theory, 8. 

10 



contained and tamed, just as nature was in the seventeenth century — transparent, 

91 

dissectible: "from music as a divine force to music as a material phenomenon." 
Music was linked with astronomy in the quadrivium and followed it from occult to 
empirical investigation: from harmony of the spheres to "disenchantment of the 

99 

world," a powerful metaphor for the cultural transformation wrought during the 
seventeenth century and played out in music. The harmony of the spheres was 

9-5 

silenced in a world "subjected to analysis and quantification." 

Before the new science was legitimized, though, experiments were carried out 
with some secrecy because of its association with natural magic. Only after the 
Restoration and with the establishment of the Royal Society did experimental science 
sufficiently separate itself from natural magic to be in the open. London became its 
intellectual center, rather than the universities, because of the Royal Society; and 
inhabiting the same intellectual spaces as experimental science, music became paired 

94 

with it, leaving behind its cosmological association with the harmony of the spheres. 

The Tuning Conundrum 

Music's move, with science, from the cosmological to the mundane universal 
meant that it was now fair game for analysis and theoretical reworking, "amenable to 



Clark and Rending, Introduction, Music Theory, 6. 

This term was apparently coined by Friedrich Schiller and famously appropriated by Max Weber 
and the Frankfurt School. In Clark and Rending, Introduction, Music Theory, 6. 
Gouk, Music, Science, 17. 
Gouk, Music, Science, 54-55. 

11 



interrogation." Scientists and theorists writing about music argued vehemently 
about a range of issues relating to music theory, none as central as the problem of 
tuning. If one begins at the tonic or root note ("do" in any key's scale) and ascends or 
descends in fifths or fourths or any other pre-determined interval, one will never 
arrive precisely at the octave. Intervals of a fifth plus a fourth, for example, should 
add up to an octave by Pythagorean reckoning; but they actually overshoot it by a bit. 
Similarly, the twelfth perfect fifth and the seventh octave from the starting point 
should culminate at the same point; but they do not. That specific discrepancy, the 
tonal distance between the twelfth perfect fifth and the seventh octave, is the 
definition of the Pythagorean comma, the core definition of the tuning problem. 
Pythagorean perfect intervals are not — perfect, that is. When music-making consisted 
of a solo instrument or voice or a cappella music, this acoustical gap was not even 
noted. But the advent of polyphonic music along with fretted and keyboard 
instruments in the Renaissance inevitably led to the discovery of "cracks in the crystal 
spheres"; accurate tuning was critical for fully exploiting the diatonic system. 7 

Equal temperament tuning simply subtracts a few oscillations from the 
supposedly perfect intervals, a bit of fudging not discernable to the average listener, 
to create twelve geometrically-derived equal semitones (each equal to the twelfth root 
of two) that are, however, irrational numbers, very far in philosophical terms from the 
supposed perfection of the arithmetic Pythagorean intervals: tuning rationality in 



Daniel Chua/' Vincenzo Galilei, modernity, and the division of nature/' in Music Theory, Clark and 
Rending, 18. 
James, Music of the Spheres, 87. 
Clark and Rending, Introduction, Music Theory, 6. 

12 



irrationality. These twelve tempered, irrational, half-tone intervals within the octave 
now add up precisely to the octave interval, a seemingly straightforward, 
uncomplicated solution. But with what cosmological significance that solution is 
freighted; and this seemingly obvious resolution of the tuning problem became 
standard practice only at the dawn of the nineteenth century. 

Music's Place in Philosophy 

Appreciating the seismic epistemological shift that equal temperament tuning 
represents involves a corresponding appreciation of music's philosophical role 
through the Renaissance. The ancient foundation of music was number, from the 
Pythagoreans in the seventh to fifth centuries BCE. Making good music meant 
choosing the right numbers: that is, creating consonances with perfect intervals. 
These intervals were defined and illustrated by a monochord (invented by Pythagoras 
himself, according to tradition), a single stretched string with a moveable bridge. The 
octave, the most consonant interval, is sounded by placing the bridge at precisely the 
middle of the monochord, creating a 1:2 ratio of total string length to compressed 
length. The interval of a fifth, the next most perfect interval, is a ratio of 2:3, and the 
fourth, the next most perfect after the fifth, is created with a 3:4 ratio. These intervals 
were the most perfect, not primarily for the sweetness of their sound, but because the 



13 



integers used to form the ratios — 1, 2, 3, and 4 — were philosophically significant for 
the Pythagoreans. 

Pythagoreans conceived a precise universe, ordered by number, against the 
materialistic universe — earth, air, water, fire — that was the focus of Aristotelian 
natural philosophy. Aristotle, in the Metaphysics, wrote of the Pythagoreans that they 
believed mathematical principles, including musical ratios, to be the foundation of 
everything, constituent elements of the whole of nature that were the ultimate reality. 
For them, nature is of mathematics and music. The noted medieval music theoretician 
Boethius (480-526) said that the Pythagoreans discovered the mathematical 
foundation of musical consonances. (Boethius himself surmised that there must be 
heavenly music because it was impossible to believe that the spheres could be moving 
silently through the heavens. ) So the philosophical connection of music to nature 
and number has very ancient roots. 30 

Music was identified with order, which was in turn identified with all of 
nature and philosophy; order inhered in the universe, expressed and organized by 
music, and was the very fabric and organizing principle of the universe. The universe 
was seen as a totality, a unity; and all knowledge, morality, and purpose were 
included in that. Man filled a meaningful and knowable, if lowly, niche in the 
cosmological unity; his purpose for existence was intimately connected to the 



The later medieval rationale for defining the fourth as dissonant was that, compared to the fifth, 
which was reinforced because of consisting of two thirds, the fourth had no such theoretical 
reinforcement. In Max Weber, The Rational and Social Foundations of Music, Trans, and ed. Don 
Martindale, Johannes Riedel, and Gertrude Neuwirth (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 
1958), 52. 
29 Murray Schafer, TheTuning of the World (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1977), 260. 

The format for this explanation is from Gozza, Number to Sound, Introduction, 1-4. 

14 



philosophical whole. The correspondence between earthly and heavenly music was 
assumed, a manifestation of connected and communicating levels of reality. All 
attempts at understanding nature were simultaneously attempts at finding man's 
rightful place in the universe; the harmony of the cosmos and morality were 
inextricable. Harmony, then, was more of a philosophical term than a musical one, 
applicable to any level of reality or of nature because of the complex system of 
correspondences and analogies that inhered in the universe. The universe was 
perfectly tuned. 

To suggest, then, that the perfect Pythagorean intervals were not perfect after 
all was not merely to point out a mildly vexing issue requiring a technical fix, as the 
problem might be framed today; it was to assault fundamental assumptions about the 
universe — the musical cosmos as the source of order, knowledge, and authority, 
giving moral meaning to man's existence — and to undermine the very foundation of 
Renaissance epistemology. The Renaissance view of the world, because it was so all- 
encompassing, did not give way easily, quickly, or by a linear route. And although the 
relentless onslaught of modernity in the seventeenth century has the certainty of 
inevitability in hindsight, by no means would it have been viewed as such by the 
century's contemporaries. Rather, the intellectual habits and ingrained ways of 
thinking about the cosmos only gradually lost intellectual cache as the new scientific 
philosophy created new questions, priorities, and criteria to judge truth as it filled the 
space left by gradually outmoded Renaissance thinking. 



James, Music of the Spheres, 12. 



15 



Four Early Philosophers on Music 

Robert Fludd and Johannes Kepler, Vincenzo Galilei and Zarlino, were on the 
cusp of this change around the change of the seventeenth century but could hardly 
have comprehended their pivotal place in intellectual history. "Thinkers and writers 
of a 'transitional' period are disadvantaged by a rather murky sense of what they are 
part of a transition to." For Fludd, the monochord so central to Pythagorean music - 
as-number philosophy was more than a scientific instrument for defining and 
measuring intervals; as we have seen in his Christianized rendering of the Divine 
Monochord, it was also the "scheme of the cosmos," the identification of the perfect 
tuning of the universe. His was the "last flowering of speculative music." Squarely 
within the Renaissance tradition, Fludd was holding fast onto a world that was 
beginning to cease to matter, obsessed with the kind of symbolic thinking that was 
antithetical to the new philosophy. 

Kepler, his contemporary and also an ardent Pythagorean-Platonist, is by 
contrast, an intriguing watershed figure, one foot squarely in the Renaissance and one 
in the new scientific epistemology; he heard the music of the spheres in full 
polyphony, "as a palpable symphony." Throughout his life, he immersed himself in 
a range of intellectual passions — astronomy, astrology, theology, mathematics — 



Mary Campbell, Wonder and Science: Imagining Worlds in Early Modern Science (Ithaca and 
London: Cornell University Press, 1999), 29. 

Gozza, Introduction, Number to Sound, 4. 

Godwin, Music, Mysticism, 105. 
35 Keith Thomas, Man and the Natural World: Changing Attitudes in England 1500-1800 (Oxford, New 
York: Oxford University Press, 1983), 67. 

James, Music of the Spheres, 140. 

16 



believing ardently in a fundamental connection among them and making it his life's 
quest to discover it. Kepler's approach was both speculative — beginning with an 
assumption of the (polyphonic) harmony of the spheres — and scientific: amassing a 
wealth of data from his meticulous astronomical observations. Initially theorizing that 
the planetary orbits could be precisely inscribed within a defined series of geometric 
solids in a glorious "Eureka" moment, he subsequently found that the astronomical 
data did not fit the theory. The scientist in him did not allow him to fudge the data, 
but the speculative Renaissance man refused to abandon his assumption of cosmic 
harmony. An ardent Christian, he believed that God must have created an alternative 
scheme that Kepler simply needed to work harder to discover. What eventually 
resulted, of course, were his laws of planetary motion, still valid today, a grand 
synthesis of Renaissance and scientific epistemologies. 

Vincenzo Galilei, father of Galileo and a generation before Fludd and Kepler, 
was sufficiently independently minded and audacious to dare to expose the 
imperfections in the Pythagorean intervals with simple experimental evidence and to 
suggest a practical solution: tempered tuning. So he was the one to deliver the 
opening salvo of the assault on Pythagorean perfection. His pronouncement came in 
the context of a battle of words with fellow scholar and intellectual nemesis, Zarlino, 
who argued strenuously against tempered tuning, insisting that singers instinctively 
use just (non-tempered) intonation because it is from nature. Vincenzo scorned this 
distinction, saying that no scale is intrinsically more natural than another. Although 



17 



he admitted that he found the just (untempered) fifth to be sweeter than the tempered 

M -JO 

one, he personally knew many musicians who preferred the tempered fifth. 

Vincenzo's position regarding tuning was highly controversial because it 
negated the idea of perfection in nature. Once that notion was dispensed with, the 
entire edifice of the harmony of the spheres was suspect. Zarlino, contemptuous of 
Vincenzo Galilei, still believed implicitly in heavenly harmony, perfection of nature, 
order, and the unity of the cosmos. He vehemently rejected the skepticism of 
Vincenzo, who contended that nature has no cognition, no intrinsic moral compass or 
exemplary models; the old ideas of consonances and supposedly perfect ratios were 
restrictive and incompatible with musical practice — not natural at all but a product of 
human rationality. The aim of music, Vincenzo argued, was not to express perfection 
but to communicate. 

The debate between the two men was extremely heated, including vicious 
personal attack: not surprising given that, although ostensibly debating the relative 
merits of just versus tempered intonation, they were in fact striving against one 
another about the nature of reality. Vincenzo's stance was the first evidence of the 
leading edge of the dispassionate view of musical philosophy and so of nature that 

in 

was to dominate the modern world. He did this in two ways: first, by objectifying 
music as a field for experimentation and, second, by acting on this knowledge to 



D. P. Walker, Studies in Musical Science in the Late Renaissance (London: the Warburg Institute, 
University of London; Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1978), 19. 
38 Walker, Studies, 113. 

Chua, "Vincenzo Galilei," in Clark and Rending, Music Theory, 17. 

18 



propose a modern system of equal temperament tuning. In pre-modern music, both 
the cosmos and the soul are tuned to Pythagorean ratios, and earthly music is a 
reflection of the celestial spheres. The cosmos is connected to earth by a monochord 
(one detailed articulation of which was Fludd's) linking the chain of being and 
imposing unity and harmony. Music was the "rational agent of enchantment." To 
reject that enchanted role of music in structuring and giving meaning to the cosmos 
was tantamount to "untuning" the cosmos. 2 It is not an exaggeration, then, to say that 
the contentious debate between Vincenzo Galilei and Zarlino was the "turning point 
of the Renaissance." 



Chua/'Vincenzo Galilei/' in Clark and Rending, Music Theory, 23. 
Chua/'Vincenzo Galilei/' in Clark and Rending, Music Theory, 22. 
Gozza, Introduction, Number to Sound, 39-41. 

19 



CHAPTER 3. MUSIC AND THE NEW PHILOSOPHY 

Through the ensuing century, the new experimental philosophy came into 
ascendance, and music was central to the story, in two somewhat different senses. 
First, as noted, music was identified with the structure of the universe in Renaissance 
thinking; so any challenge to the central role of music in cosmology of was 
tantamount to challenging epistemological beliefs. Second, with the growing 
importance of polyphonic and instrumental music by the eve of the seventeenth 
century, the tuning problem had to be addressed. 

Because of its importance in the intellectual conversation of the time, 
experimental natural philosophers devised experiments and wrote about music, 
though usually not as an end in itself. These included Francis Bacon, at the beginning 
of the century, Robert Hooke at mid-century, and Isaac Newton writing Principia and 
his later unpublished scholia. The Royal Society, a gathering of gentlemen scholars 
chartered by Charles II in 1660 and pledged to taking up the gauntlet thrown down by 
Bacon to construct a new edifice of natural philosophy through experimental 
investigation and observation, participated in the musical conversation by offering a 
forum for discussion of musical experiments. 

Aside from the well-known experimental philosophers, less noted musical 
theorists wrote about music as a central concern, not as a way to elucidate other 
scientific ideas or to explore the nature of sound. These (mostly) men created an 
edifice of basic music theory that stands almost unchanged to this day, but also 
engaged in protracted debates with proffered solutions for a range of musical issues, 

20 



including the tuning problem. These musical theorists were more narrowly focused 
than the new natural philosophers who had only incidental interests in music. They 
did, nonetheless, respond, think, and write within the same epistemologically shifting 
milieu as the greater philosophers; and their musical writing, as an art product, is also 
a source of illumination about that tumult. 

Each offers hints about the complex, non-linear, even at times retrograde route 
by which the new philosophy became "epistemologically privileged discourse" 43 and 
the way music figured in the grand conversation which was ultimately about sources 
of authority and order. Musical writing illuminates challenges to the Renaissance 
notions of the harmonic and moral structure of the cosmos and changing attitudes 
toward nature: from an organic, unitary whole making up the Great Chain of Being 
with humanity having its place in that continuum, to humans as the objective 
observers of nature, experimenting and investigating to reveal its secrets. 

Three Natural Philosophers on Music 

Bacon 

The name most firmly linked to the beginning of that is surely Francis Bacon, 
and as such he warrants particular attention. Bacon's early polemical tracts and the 
longer, more fully-developed works of his later years set the agenda for early 
experimental science and served as the methodological foundation of the Royal 
Society after the Restoration. In a century marked by the coexistence of still-robust 



Clark and Rending, Introduction, Music Theory, 8. 



21 



Renaissance ideas alongside startlingly new philosophical notions, Bacon's writing 
stands as a metaphor for the creation of new intellectual spaces. His experimental 
methodology is often cited as the hallmark of the revolution he helped lead; but his 
project transcended mere methodology to initiate a repositioning of man in relation to 
the cosmos and an alteration of the very foundation of order. 

Had he foreseen the epistemological shift initiated by the new experimental 
philosophy as it was to meet the powerfully fragmenting religious and political forces 
of the century, Bacon may have given serious pause to his strident advocacy of his 
philosophical agenda. He unquestioningly embraced Renaissance thinking even as he 
advocated for the new philosophy. Natural magic, an experiment-based enterprise, 
flourished along with scientific investigation in that century, with no clear distinction 
made initially. Bacon himself was firmly planted in his own time, holding onto 
ideas about nature and natural phenomena that would later appear scientifically 
absurd — ideas which his own proposed methodology would help dismantle. He 
unabashedly betrays magical Renaissance thinking even as he writes about his new 
philosophy. In Sylva Sylvarum particularly, Bacon reveals the extent of his magical 
and alchemical thinking, incorporating unselfconsciously an astonishing array of 
magical beliefs into his explanations. Though heralded as scientific innovator and 



Charles Webster, From Paracelsus to Newton: Magic and the Making of Modern Science 
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), 2. 

Richard Foster Jones, ed., Francis Bacon: Essays, Advancement of Learning, New Atlantis and Other 
Pieces (New York: The Odyssey Press, 1937), xxviii. 

Paolo Rossi, Francis Ba< 
Chicago Press, 1968), 12. 

22 



Paolo Rossi, Francis Bacon: From Magic to Science, trans. Sacha Rabinovitch (Chicago: University of 



reformist, Bacon drew heavily on "medieval and Renaissance traditions of natural 

4-7 

knowledge." 

Nevertheless, clear differences distinguish Renaissance natural magic and the 
new natural philosophy, consigning the one to historical obscurity and the other to 
philosophical dominance by the end of the century. The former focuses on the 
unusual and the occult, promoting a sense of mystery, the latter on the ordinary and 
revealed book of nature, striving for transparency and the resolution of mystery. Still, 
because of the persistence of magical beliefs and natural magic's experimental 
methodology, the new philosophy (and Bacon, grudgingly) found common cause with 
natural magic, the two coexisting in a shifting intellectual space for most of the 
seventeenth century as natural magic gradually but inevitably lost intellectual cache 
even as the new philosophy gained intellectual ascendancy. 

While natural magic had its ascendancy in the Renaissance, Aristotelian 
philosophy dominated the pre-Renaissance centuries; and Scholasticism continued to 
be taught in the universities through the first part of the seventeenth century. Bacon 
had only scorn for the failure of Aristotelian natural philosophy to actively investigate 
nature to discover cause and effect and for relying instead on pointless argumentation 
to no useful end. Aristotle is the "Prince of Imposture. . .the Anti-Christ". . .who failed 
to "practice serious study and observation of natural phenomena, which are the only 



Richard Serjeantson, "Natural Knowledge in The New Atlantis," in Francis Bacon's New Atlantis: 
New Interdisciplinary Essays , ed. Bronwen Price (Manchester, New York: Manchester University 
Press, 2002), 84. 

23 



basis of philosophy." Nature must be discovered through the (admittedly limited) 
senses, aided by experimental method. Aristotelian rationalization is utterly fruitless 
and "does not produce discoveries, but. . .crushes and extinguishes them." 49 For the 
new experimental philosophy, Bacon envisions a marriage of nature and the rational 
faculties, radically divorced in Aristotle's philosophy. "Let us establish a chaste and 
lawful marriage between Mind and Nature. . . [that] from that marriage may issue 
. . .wholesome and useful inventions. . . ." 50 

Bacon's contempt for Aristotelian philosophy and its intellectual handmaiden, 
Scholasticism — words without actions, nature without investigation, talking without 
doing 5 —made Bacon hypothesis-shy. He insisted that the aim of his new philosophy 
is the discovery of nature, not the construction of theoretical edifices. His idea of 
reform for natural philosophy entails the construction of a complete natural history 
from the active investigation of nature before any theory-construction. Bacon's curt 
dismissal of scholasticism and alchemy — "the one never faileth to multiply words and 
the other ever faileth to multiply gold" — epitomizes his contempt. The role of 
hypothesis in scientific investigation, now virtually unquestioned, was contentious in 
the seventeenth century because of its connection to Aristotelian speculative natural 
philosophy. 



Francis Bacon, "The Refutation of Philosophies/' in The Philosophy of Francis Bacon, ed. Benjamin 
Farrington (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1964), 113, 115. 
Bacon, "Refutation," in Farrington, 125. 
Bacon, "Refutation," in Farrington, 131. 
Serjeantson, "Natural Knowledge," in Price, 85. 
Bacon, Discourse in Praise of Knowledge, in Farrington, 15. 

24 



Scorn for Scholasticism, that complex, rationalist enterprise to reconcile the 
teachings of the Church and Aristotle, prompted Bacon to insist on a rigid separation 
of theology and philosophy. It was not a war between the two he fears, but rather an 
unhealthy entwining of the two, such as had dominated Western philosophy and 
theology for centuries. He saw this mingling of science and religion as pernicious. 
Bacon continually emphasized the need to distinguish between Creator and Creation, 
between God and nature. Failure to do so was a fatal flaw of the ancients in their 
relationship with nature. Nature is evidence, but not the image, of God and must not 
be reverenced. It is indifferent to humans; so humans must impose art on nature to 
harness it for the good of humanity. Nature itself neither "make[s] moral sense" nor 
"exhibits] divine care." 54 Mixing the two conflates and confuses the divine with the 
natural and blurs the distinction between religion and science. 55 

Early on, Bacon presided over a firm separation of the new natural philosophy 
from the religious enterprise, a bifurcation within natural philosophy, with all its 
unresolved tensions, that has persevered to this day. Nonetheless, religion was the 
primary concern of most people in the seventeenth century. So nature joined Scripture 
as a new foundation of truth about God and the universe. Theories were reworked in 
the language of the New Science. These reworkings were normative in the way the 
old ones had been. New philosophers believed that investigation into nature would 
confirm Scripture's veracity and thus bolster faith. The reformulations advocated not 



Rossi, Francis Bacon, 97. 
54 Jerry Weinberger, "On the Miracles in Bacon's New Atlantis," in Price, 117-118. 
Rossi, Francis Bacon, 44. 

25 



a break with religion, but adding nature as another field of divine revelation in this 
religious era. 5 This framing of new science helped legitimize it and armor it against 
accusations of atheism. 

Still, the storm clouds of vague associations with atheism hovered 
threateningly over the new philosophy; Bacon was prescient about the potentially 
awesome power of technology born of the manipulation of nature and believed that it 
must be tempered with and guided by knowledge of God, a moral restraint he would 
have assumed to be permanent and secure. He himself is "uncertainly suspended" 
between atomism — materialistic but with the taint of atheism — and Stoical theory of 
pneuma — uncomfortably close to reintroducing divinity into nature, philosophically 
untenable. But the cautionary religiosity Bacon saw as a permanent part of this re- 
alignment was eroded and eventually destroyed by his own methodology; and so too 
notions of order became severed from morality and religion to become strictly 
human-fashioned. Regardless of Bacon's own misgivings, the notion of an inert 
nature with the rejection of God immanent in nature set the agenda for the 
seventeenth century and is intimately linked to evolving concepts of order and 
authority. Bacon continually emphasizes the necessity of distinguishing between the 

CO 

Creator and His Creation and nature's moral indifference. 



Roy Porter, "Creation and Credence: The Career of Theories of the Earth in Britain, 1600-1820," in 
Natural Order: Historical Studies of Scientific Culture, eds. Barry Barnes and Steven Shapin (Thousand 
Oaks: SAGE Publications, 1979), 98. 
"Weinberger, "Miracles," in Price, 115. 

Weinberger, "Miracles," in Price, 117-118. Also, early modern science was almost entirely a male 
pursuit. The fact that medieval institutions, most notably the hegemonic Church, were the exclusive 
realm of men meant that the institutions that grew out of that tradition continued to be dominated 
by males. Because of the clerical origins of early modern science, the "conceptual and ideological 

26 



In music this meant a movement away from music as number to music as 
sound. Bacon stoutly rejects the notion of the harmony of the spheres and Platonic 
ratios as the foundation of the cosmos. Since physical, not mathematical, 
investigation of the universe is his aim, music is a sensible acoustic event, not a 
source of mathematical speculations. This Platonic rejection, ironically, mimics 
Aristotle, who also rejected philosophical notions of cosmic harmony. Both Aristotle 
and Bacon, though, adhered to other Platonic ideas including a universe based on 
order and proportion and a belief in the moral and emotional power of music. 

Bacon's approach to music and sound, in fact, incorporates natural magic as 
well as experimental philosophy. He thinks music can be used for Utopian ends 
through science and technology and is the first to propose a program for the empirical 
investigation of sound through a mix of "observation, imitation and manipulation of 
nature," 60 detailed in Salomon's House in The New Atlantis. This work draws heavily 
on "medieval and Renaissance traditions of natural knowledge." l Though its setting 
is fantastical, Bacon insists this work is not a Utopian vision but rather a realizable 
goal for a society properly employing technology for the good of humanity. The 
paragraph on sound-houses describes a magical-technological approach to 
investigation: 

structure" of medieval institutions remained intact regarding gender roles. Bacon strove to break the 
fetters of traditional Aristotelian philosophy; challenging gender roles too would likely have been 
beyond his ability to comprehend. In Revolutionizing the Sciences: European Knowledge and Its 
Ambitions, 1500-1700, Peter Dear (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2001), 16. 

Gouk, "Music in Francis Bacon's Natural Philosophy," in Gozza, 136. 
60 Gouk, "Music," in Gozza, 137. 

Richard Serjeantson, "Natural Knowledge" in Price, 84. 

James Spedding, Preface to The New Atlantis, in The Works of Francis Bacon, Vol. V, eds. James 
Spedding, Robert Leslie Ellis, and Douglas Denon Heath (New York: Houghton Mifflin, 1904), 351. 

27 



We have also sound houses, where we practice and demonstrate all 
sounds and their generation. We have harmonies. . ..Diverse 
instruments of music... We represent small sounds as great and deep; 
likewise great sounds extenuate and sharp; we make divers trembling 
and warbling of sounds.... We represent and imitate all articulate 
sounds and letters, and the voices and notes of beasts and birds. We 
have certain helps which set to the ear do further the hearing greatly. 
We have also divers strange and artificial echos, reflecting the voice 
many times. . . .We have also means to convey sounds in trunks and 
pipes, in strange lines. 63 

Bacon writes more generally about music as part of his plan for the new 

natural philosophy. In Sylva Sylvarum, divided into ten centuries, each containing 100 

experiments, Century II focuses on music. The introductory paragraph is the most 

famous of Bacon's observations on music: 

Music, in the practice, hath been well pursued, and in good variety; but 
in the theory, and especially in the yielding of the causes of the 
practique, very weakly; being reduced into certain mystical subtilties, 
of no use and not much truth. We shall, therefore, after our manner, 
join the contemplative and active part together. 64 

Bacon has little use for the elaborate structure of Renaissance music theory, 

based on Pythagorean intervals and mystical number relationships. As in all of his 

natural philosophy, he wants to investigate the causes — of musical sound, in this case. 

He agrees with theorists that the octave is the most consonant interval — "The 

diapason or eighth in music is the sweetest concord" — but says "the cause is dark, 

and hath not been rendered by any." Bacon, who ostensibly seems "perverse" in 

claiming ignorance in his Sylva Sylvarum of the octave-unison relationship, for 



63 Bacon, Works, Vol. V, 407. 
Francis Bacon, Sylva Sylvarum, "Century II," in Works, Vol. IV, 225. 
Bacon, Sylva Sylvarum, in Works, Vol. IV, 226. 

28 



example, since the foundation for Platonic intervals was well-known, is actually 
merely admitting he does not know about the connection between frequency of 
vibration and pitch, a discovery just making its appearance on the intellectual 
horizon. 7 He goes on to suggest it must be that the air is forced into a regular pattern 
to give the sweet sound of the octave. In the matter of the two half-tones of the 
major scale, Bacon says "the varying is natural. . .required" by nature. So much for 
causes. 

Bacon agrees with Renaissance theorists in the order of the sweetness of 
interval consonances, except about the interval of the fourth. The question of the 
consonance of this interval was much debated, but composers of polyphonic music 
needed it and were using it freely. Bacon favors the fourth as consonant, claiming 
accord with ancient tradition. "The concords in music which are perfect. . .are the 
fifth. . .the third. . .the sixth. . .and, as the ancients esteemed, and so do myself and 
some other yet, the fourth, which they call the diatessaron." This is the pragmatic 
stance, admitting what was already virtually standard in musical practice. 

Study of consonances was of paramount concern to Bacon, as to every writer 
on music in the seventeenth century. In an intriguing discussion about the causes of 
sweetness of sound, Bacon makes an analogy with sight. "There be two things 
pleasing to the sight... colours and order." The pleasure of color is analogous to the 



66 Walker, Studies, 120. 
Gouk. Music, Science, 167. 

68 Bacon, Sylva, in Works, Vol. IV, 227. 

69 Bacon, Sylva, in Works, Vol. IV, 227-228. 

70 Bacon, Sylva, in Works, Vol. IV, 228. 



29 



sweetness of a single tone, but the pleasure of order "doth symbolise with harmony." 
Garden knots, good proportion, and symmetrical figures please; while irregular 

71 

shapes are "deformities." Harmony equals beauty equals order. Order is loved, even 
revered, all the more so as the desperate hope of an early- seventeenth-century society 
seeming to be losing its unitary way amidst religious and political divisions. "But to 

79 

find the proportion of that correspondence [harmony], is more abstruse," — an 
inquiry for another day, apparently, as Bacon does not investigate causes of harmony 
in Sylva Sylvarum. 

He addresses the issue of musical sound though, describing experiments with 

"7-5 

various materials and instruments to produce a variety of pitches but omitting, 
interestingly, any reference to the monochord. He is either ignorant of it or thinks, 
perhaps, the reference touches too closely on mystical Pythagorean number intervals. 
The intervening and concluding observations describe the creation and transmission 
of sound and its connection with the percussion of air and vibration. A seemingly 
glaring omission is any discussion of the tuning problem, becoming acute because of 
the prevalence of both polyphonic music and fretted and keyboard instruments. 
Instead, Bacon's century on music, though freely drawing on other sources as does all 
of Sylva Sylvarum, focuses on finding causes for observed phenomena through 
experimentation. 



71 Bacon, Sylva, in Works, Vol. IV, 229-230. 

72 Bacon, Sylva, in Works, Vol. IV, 230. 

73 Bacon, Sylva, in Works, Vol. IV, 257-261. 



30 



In disentangling Aristotelian philosophy from Christianity, Bacon unwittingly 
aided and abetted the sowing of the seeds of secularization by participating in the 
fragmentation of authority begun with the Protestant reformation. It is an outcome 
Bacon himself would have stridently condemned. Others through the century 
participated in the subordination of mystical Platonic and Pythagorean philosophy in 
favor of scientific knowledge as the criterion for authority; virtually all of them too 
would have strenuously decried the materialistic, secularizing consequences of that 
action. And that is the ironic story of early modernity: the fragmentation of sources of 
authority and order, borne of an altered relationship to nature and sincere religious 
sentiment. 

Hooke 

Later in the century, Robert Hooke was the consummate experimental 
investigator. As Robert Boyle's assistant in the 1650s (pre-Royal Society), he devised 
mechanisms for conducting Boyle's own experiments. The most famous was, of 
course, the air pump, later to become a mainstay of Royal Society discussions and 
experimentation. His enthusiasm for experimentation was recognized by the Royal 
Society, which named him the first Curator of Experiments and later Secretary of the 
Society after Oldenburg's death in 1677. In his experimental mode, Hooke relied on 
hypothesis-testing, drawing sharp criticism from Newton, who saw this methodology 
as anti-empirical, muddying the waters by proposing imaginary, contrary 
explanations for natural phenomena already confirmed by experiment and 



31 



observation. 7 Hooke in turn upbraided Newton for his (Newton's) dogmatism in 
stating with absolute certainty, for example, that he had proved his theory of optics 
and proposing his own alternate hypothesis for the data. 

But far from being a dilettante, Hooke was an ingenious tinkerer, finding 
creative solutions to practical problems. 7 Even though he advocated a mathematical 
approach to the development of natural philosophy, his forte was inventing devices to 

77 

further the cause of useful experimentation. He helped advance the field of 
microscopy for his magnum opus, Micrographia (1665), one of the few books 
published under the auspices of the Royal Society. Also, Hooke found that he 
required a better light source than a simple candle or lamp to properly enhance the 
image from the microscope. His answer — the sotoscope, a liquid-filled glass globe 
placed between light source and microscope and focused with a convex lens to direct 
the intensified light on to the specimen. Hooke was not unaware of his creative 
gifts. On more than one occasion, he claimed to have found a clock-based solution to 

7Q 

that Holy Grail of seventeenth-century science, the longitude problem. While 
acknowledging that the senses were prone to "narrowness and wandering," he had 



Peter B. Anstey, "Experimental Versus Speculative Natural Philosophy/' in The Science of Nature: 
Patterns of Change in Early Modern Natural Philosophy, eds. Peter Anstey and John A. Schuster (The 
Netherlands: Dordrecht, 2005), 229, 232. 

Steven Shapin, The Scientific Revolution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998), 115-116. 
75 Marcus Hellyer, The Scientific Revolution (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, Ltd, 2003), 195. Hellyer 
maintains that twentieth-century historians of the scientific revolution fail to appreciate the extent to 
which seventeenth-century natural philosophers pursued science to solve practical problems. 
77 Hellyer, Scientific Revolution, 180-181. 

Lisa Jardin, Ingenious Pursuits: Building the Scientific Revolution (New York: Random House, Inc., 
1999), 44. 

Jardin, Ingenious, 51. It was not until the latter part of the eighteenth century that John Harrison 
found a clock-based solution to that vexing problem of navigation. In Longitude, Dava Sobel 
(Middlesex, England: Penguin Books, Ltd., 1996). 

32 



confidence that instruments such as the microscope and telescope would adequately 
compensate for these shortcomings. 

Hooke thought about more than experiments, though. He believed that the 
ancients possessed great philosophical truth, but that it had become severely 
compromised over time. "It is said of great Empires, that the best way to preserve 
them from decay, is to bring them back to the first Principles. . .on which they did 

01 

begin. The same is undoubtedly true in Philosophy." Like most other natural 
philosophers of the time, Hooke professed a personal godliness and religiosity. Under 
his microscope lens, he saw revealed such perfect adaptation between structure and 
function that he wondered how anyone could "think all those things the production of 
chance." Also coincident with most of his peers in natural philosophy, Hooke 
believed the purpose of natural philosophical knowledge was to "erect a glorious and 
everlasting structure to nature" and thus nature's Creator. 

Musical investigation constituted an important part of Hooke 's experimental 
agenda, mostly relating to the nature of sound, ranging from vibrations and acoustics 
to the nature of harmonious intervals and the effects of music. He understood sound 
as vibration and, more importantly, related frequency to pitch in his experiments. 
Most of Hooke's musical experiments were presented to the Royal Society in 1664. 
In addition to the experiments presented to the Royal Society, Hooke presented 
papers focused more on the effects of music to a secret Philosophical Club, formed in 



Shapin, Scientific Revolution, 93. 
Hooke, quoted in Shapin, Scientific Revolution, 75. 
Hooke, quoted in Shapin, Scientific Revolution, 144. 
Hooke, quoted in Shapin, Scientific Revolution, 153. 



33 



the mid- 1670s by Hooke and others, including Christopher Wren and William 
Holder, interested in musical topics. In papers probably prepared for this group, 
Hooke hypothesized that nature has constructed the ear to receive sound exactly as it 
is produced, that is, in the same frequency. The consonant intervals (octave, fifth, 
fourth, etc.) are pleasing and harmonious, not because of mystical Pythagorean 
numbers, but because these are the frequencies that strike the ear in a "coincidence of 
the Vibrations." Rhythm "is that which is most active and operative upon the 
affections & passions of men." Harmony, though, offers the "most ravishing pleasure 
& delight of all." It is an intellectual pleasure because the mind must sort out the 
mathematical intricacies of the music to make it pleasurable. This is possible because 
God has created both the world and humans according to mathematical, geometric 
principles. 85 

Hooke, along with Newton, saw music as the underlying structure of the 
universe, 86 an idea that seemed to peacefully co-exist with his cutting-edge 
experimentation on vibration theory. He constructed musical models, not primarily to 
explain musical principles, but to elucidate his natural philosophy in the context of 
this larger notion of the "harmonic structure of the universe," with mathematics as the 
connecting vector. This notion is, of course, essentially Pythagorean; and Hooke 
unabashedly subscribed to this Renaissance idea to design experiments and create 



Hooke, "Curious Dissertation concerning the Causes of the Powers and Effects of Music/' in Gouk, 
Music, Science, 200 and 207-209. Hooke also prepared a series of "Musick Scripts" to discuss his 
ideas, likely for the Philosophical Club. 

Hooke, "Curious," in Gouk, Music, Science, 212-213. 

Gouk, Music, Science, 225. 

Gouk, Music, Science, 213. 

34 



explanations: music as a means to an end rather than an end in itself. Most notably, he 
compared the minute particles constituting matter to the action of vibrating strings to 
explain the nature of matter and conducted experiments in acoustics and musical 

QQ 

vibration to articulate and fortify his own theory of vibrating matter. Again, he used 
musical analogies when detailing his theory of color by comparing the spectrum to 
musical harmonies and his notion of light by comparison to sound waves. 

Hooke also weighed in on musical issues in their own right, including musical 
notation and division of the scale. His approach was, typically, a combination of 
Pythagorean mysticism and experimental practicality, his ideas on these matters 
based on widely held ideas of the time, not original but rather his own unique 
presentation. Whether to give names to the twelve tones of the octave and what those 
names should be was one much-discussed (though hardly pivotal) musical issue of the 
time. Hooke suggested a system of musical notation as an attempt to simplify and 
rationalize both reading and composing music. The division of the scale, an issue 
closely touching on the tuning conundrum, pre-occupied mathematicians and 
theorists; and it is clear that Hooke was aware of others' geometrical and irrational- 
number calculations for the scale divisions. Though acknowledging the necessity of 
some kind of temperament tuning for practical musical production, Hooke never went 
so far in musical theorizing as to offer any solution of his own devising; and he 



Gouk, Music, Science, 214, 218. 
89 Gouk, Music, Science, 201, 216. 



35 



maintained that the true intervals were of just intonation (Pythagorean plus additional 
consonant intervals advocated by Zarlino). 



Newton 

Much greater even than Hooke, Newton wrote that masterwork of Western 
mathematical logic, Prinicipia mathematica (1687), but was loath to publish it. His 
friend Edmund Halley persuaded him to do so by paying for its publication under the 
auspices of the Royal Society. Newton was a serious investigator of alchemy and 
considered his alchemical studies to be the core of his life's work. His volumes of 
writing mostly concern his astrological and alchemical investigations and 
speculations; and his personal library included mostly books on these subjects and 
only a few on the new scientific philosophy. 

The initial work on Prinicipia mathematica (1687), as well as Newton's 
discovery of the law of gravity, was a product of his anno mirabilis, the year Newton 
spent at home when Cambridge was closed for fear of the plague. Newton, though, 
saw both of these scientific-mathematical accomplishments in terms of their value in 
penetrating the meaning of Pythagoras' celestial harmony; the Pythagorean musical 

no 

ratios underlay his inverse square law. According to Newton's scholia, both the 
inverse square law and the law of gravity were adumbrated by the prisci theologi in 



Gouk, Music, Science, 201. 



The Royal Society, however, lacked the funds to repay Halley, so recompensed him with multiple 
copies of Francis Willoughby's Historic/ piscium, a lavishly illustrated non-seller published by the 
Society the year before. In Ingenious, Jardine, 36. 

James, Music of the Spheres, 160. 

Gozza, Number to Sound, 50. 

36 



the mists of antiquity. This consummate man of science and mathematics, the very 
epitome of seventeenth-century brilliance, viewed his monumental intellectual 
creations as mere re-interpretations of ancient encoded wisdom. 

Not surprisingly, Newton's interest in music was based on mathematics. He 
developed his own system for the division of the scale, a task exercising theorists 
mightily because of its intimate connection with the tuning problem. Newton devised 
a chart of logarithmically calculated tempered semitones that anticipates almost 
precisely that in use today. He seems more interested in the mathematical 
complexities and creating symmetry than in aural considerations; and he is anxious to 
construct a system of intervals, by theorizing tiny building blocks of sound, that is 
closest to classical just intonation. Newton's musical theorizing is a part of his 
obsession with mystical number manipulation relating to ancient wisdom rather than 
a desire to derive some practical solution for the temperament problem facing 
practicing musicians. He used his acoustical work to inform his optical investigations, 
drawing an analogy (as others also did) between the musical scale and the color 
spectrum. 

Newton, following Pythagoras, believed the cosmos to be structured by 
mathematics, evident in Principia, and himself as an agent to recover ancient 
theological wisdom. His investigation into the harmonics of both music and color was 
part of his lifelong attempt to reveal the true basis of the harmony of the spheres, the 



94 Walker, Studies, 25. 
Gouk, Music, Science, 233. 
Gouk, Music, Science, 235, 237. 



37 



truth of which had been encoded to hide it from the vulgar but symbolically and 
allegorically decipherable by a true philosopher such as Newton himself. The musical 
scale and the color spectrum relate to the actual harmony of the heavens, not the 
literal creation of tones by the motion of crystal spheres, but the entire mathematical 

Q7 

edifice underlying the cosmos. Newton saw himself, not as a discoverer of new 
truths about the working of the universe, but as one revealing its ancient, encoded 
wisdom. Absolute space was, to Newton, God's "universal sensorium." " 



97 Gouk, Music, Science, 251-254. 

Peter Dear, Revolutionizing the Sciences: European Knowledge and Its Ambitions, 1500—1700 
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2001), 169. 

38 



CHAPTER 4. HUMANITY CREATING ITS OWN MEANING 

Implicit within the century's changing perspectives on nature as they inform 
altered sources of authority and order is the notion that humans now have chosen to 
make do for themselves. The cosmos is delineated, humanity is in the ascendant, 
nature is knowable and controllable — a pyrrhic victory, exacted at the cost of the 
severing of once-vital connections: between nature and morality, meaning and spirit, 
science and philosophy. Humanity's pride in its newfound control of nature and 
authority, wresting power from a spiritually imbued cosmos to bring to earth as its 
own provenance, wraps the onus in the guise of a gift of increasing scientific 
hegemony. From now on, humankind itself must operate without reference to the 
harmony of the spheres. If there is to be harmony, humanity must be both originator 
and guarantor. On its own in the cosmos, no longer part of a great chain of being 
ensconced within a unique niche of the natural world, no longer dependent on a 
shared notion of cosmic harmony, rather relying on its own power to create and 
sustain, to order and deliver, to provide and satisfy — humanity is the ultimate source 
for all its own physical, intellectual, and spiritual needs. 

One initially compelling metaphor maintains that the traditional religious 
ideology underlying the new theory of nature in the seventeenth century is the basso 
continue), supporting the status quo; new lyrics and melody are the changes in 



39 



philosophy and religion that play over it. But the basso continuo was not left 
unchanged, even if the moral-religious ethos remained strong. Though not apparent 
early in the seventeenth century, the moral and the religious were destined to be only 
vestiges, however sincerely proclaimed, that eventually revealed their uselessness to 
the new natural philosophy; the new basso continuo is the modern scientific 
enterprise: materialistic, radically divorced from religion, ideologically neutral. The 
source of morality, religion, and ideology no longer lies with the cosmos; humans 
now have the freedom, or bear the burden, of fashioning these anew — for each 
individual and for society. It is a human-made world, in much more than a merely 
technological sense. This new way of thinking about nature was part of a deep and 
wide shift within society — political, philosophical, and religious — recognizing that 
humanity, without recourse to the immutable heavens, must now be in control of its 
own destiny, including the awful freedom to choose among diverse sources of 
authority and order. 

This new natural philosophy was not just about changing methodology. New 
ideas about nature and man's relationship to it redefine order and authority, a true 
epistemological shift. But in no sense was it a linear one. Renaissance-era beliefs in 
analogies and correspondences continued to be culturally meaningful even as the 
scientific revolution proceeded apace. This contradictory, complex seismic shift can 
be viewed through artistic products as they reveal, though opaquely, 100 prevailing 



Porter, "Creation and Credence/' in Barnes and Shapin, Natural Order, 101. 
Sharpe, Remapping, 40. 

40 



beliefs, concerns, and desires, expressing illusions as well as anxieties. 1 l Reading 
cultural texts for ideological meaning is critical for the seventeenth century in 
particular because political thought and language did not even exist as a distinct, 
discrete level of discourse until the latter part of the century and because the 
participants in the profound shift of cultural meanings in the seventeenth century were 
utterly unaware of the transformational enterprise of which they were a part. So the 
upheavals of the seventeenth century, far from being transparently expressed in 
cultural products, often led to a "forceful articulation of organic unity" as writers 
agonized about their fear of disorder in the face of disintegrating certainties or, later 
in the century, more easily embraced the new epistemology identified by 
fragmentation of sources of authority and truth as old meanings and attachments 
mattered less and less. 

Music Central to That Change 

Music figures critically in this epic shift in having become, through evolution, 
hard- wired into the human brain, a source of social cohesion since humanity's pre- 
history. All known societies have had music; it is intimately connected with the 
development of language, dating to the beginning of our species. Music is central 
to what it means to be human; so the musical conversation of the seventeenth century 
is even more heavily freighted with meaning than just one among any number of 



Sharpe, Remapping, 29. 
Sharpe, Remapping, 48. 
Sharpe, Remapping, 49. 
Oliver Sacks, Musicophilia (New York: Random House, Inc., 2007), x. 

41 



other cultural expressions as political statements. Musical writing, however narrowly 
focused, is yet accessing a deep human reservoir of meaning of sources of order and 
authority. As humans assumed increasing autonomy, this epic shift is encoded in 
music thinking and writing. 

Changing Ideas of Nature in Music Writing 

That dividing line of seventeenth-century English history, the Civil War, was 
a cultural break in forcing the polity to confront the fact of fragmentation and loss of 
harmony; but it was not the cause or even the symptom of a sharp break in that belief 
in a unified and harmonic society. That had been eroding for some time, as evidenced 
in the temperament controversy in music. The realization that there was a problem 
with the intervals as pronounced by Pythagoras was known by those who worked in 
music; and with that realization came inevitable enormous cosmological implications: 
the harmony of the spheres was not as advertised. As musical theorists and 
practitioners grappled with the temperament problem, the out-of-sync intervals 
pointed to more questions, and questioning, about other accepted truths concerning 
the physical universe — the great chain of being and man's niche within it — along 
with more mundane but pressing matters of politics and society. 

The new realizations and realities in society and philosophy meant that 
humankind was severing its spiritual ties to nature and cosmos, arrogating to itself the 
roles previously belonging to a sacralized universe, thus desacralizing those functions 
as they came within the realm of human-created control and authority. Though 



42 



musical treatise writers reveal an increasing sense of mastery as well as continuing 
anxiety about shifting cosmology through the century, the changes are highly 
contested and non-linear. 

The Royal Society tended to attract men (and only men of course) with a 
range of interests pertaining to the new experimental philosophy, including music as a 
means of elucidating other ideas and occasionally musical topics per se. Musical 
theorists were not stalwarts of the Society (though they occasionally had their papers 
on music theory topics presented for discussion), but rather focused their attention 
and writing on musical topics as ends in themselves; and there was much to contend 
with, during the century when most modern music theory was developed, within the 
roiling context of what to do about tuning. While the major natural philosophers 
addressed music in a multi-faceted, global sense for a variety of aims, musical 
theorists were, by contrast, singularly focused on music in a strictly theoretical sense 
in which it was central to the story of natural philosophy in the seventeenth century. 
Where the Royal Society elites articulated a broad range of interest in scientific topics 
related to the new philosophy and occasionally includied music because of its 
connection to other kinds of knowledge, the musical theorists pursued defined aims of 
developing music theory as they grappled with the tuning problem for polyphonic and 
instrumental music. The groups overlap, of course; but this second were most known 
as musicians and musical theorists, rather than natural philosophers who occasionally 



43 



wrote about music. The musical structures developed by these theorists is nothing less 
than "ideology. . .encoded in symbolic systems" and so worthy of investigation. 

Though scholasticism was still being taught in the universities into the 
seventeenth century, neo-Platonism dominated Renaissance thought and launched the 
seventeenth century, implicit in all institutions. If new-Platonism was concerned with 
"the realization of perfect forms," then the purpose of art was to demonstrate the 
perfection in nature. As the foundation of beliefs about nature began shifting, art 
became one site of contention about the Platonic ideals, questioning a moral, 
meaningful, organic cosmos and the authority of the heavens in human affairs. 
Musical writers advocated a variety of solutions to musical theoretical problems, 
reflecting and revealing the shifting bases of philosophical beliefs through their 
writing about music. 

Questioning the neo-Platonic notion of the harmony of the spheres as a 
metaphor for the heavens as source of order and authority for humanity coincided 
with the changing notions of nature. As beliefs about nature dictate beliefs about 
music, so music was central to the questioning of old assumptions, though in mostly 
oblique ways. Musical writers did not set out to debate deep philosophical questions 
of meaning and authority; but their contentious writing was an active site for that 
debate, albeit unwittingly, and all the more so because the problem with Platonic 
intervals, the tuning problem, was of necessity so central to their discussion. 



Sharpe, Remapping, 94. 
Sharpe, Remapping, 448. 



44 



Harmony of the spheres — rife with correspondences in reflected realities of 
heaven and earth; an ordered and interconnected universe of hierarchy and beauty; an 
opaque, sacralized cosmos saturated with meaning and significance — was 
"metaphysically dependent" on neo-Platonic ideas. 7 This universe was in sharp 
contrast to that which underlay the new philosophy. The latter demanded 
"taxonomical" structure in the universe, its meaning transparent to human 
investigation and experiment. Neo-Platonism was at cross-purposes to the new 
philosophy and lost its central role; it was not so much attacked as dismissed. With 
one foot still in the Renaissance, Bacon, at the beginning of the century, had tried to 
reconcile the new philosophy with neo-Platonism; and Newton, at the end of the 
century, was still pre-occupied with Platonic-based pursuits. But by the end of the 
seventeenth century, neo-Platonism simply lost intellectual cache, out of joint with 
the times. "The [late] seventeenth-century neo-Platonic revival was... a doomed 
attempt to reinvest an already fatally secular cosmos with the sense of sacred 
home." ( The description of the cosmos envisioned by neo-Platonism was no longer 
seen as useful. 

The Platonic ideal in music dictated that the perfect intervals were to be 
combined into compositions according to strict parameters based on consonances 
emanating from God and nature, to be discovered by man. The ancient foundation of 
music was number, as discovered by Pythagoras. Making good music meant choosing 



Geneva, Astrology, 269. 
Geneva, Astrology, 271. 
Geneva, Astrology, 282. 



45 



the right numbers, the correct intervals to create perfect consonances. 1 1 The 
Pythagoreans conceived of this precise, number-ordered universe against the 
materialistic universe of Aristotelian natural philosophy. Aristotle himself wrote of 
the Pythagoreans that they believed mathematical principles, including musical ratios, 
to be the constituent elements of the whole of nature, the ultimate reality. Boethius 
(480-526) re-iterated that Pythagoras discovered the mathematical foundation of 
musical consonances in the perfect intervals. Mathematics is the foundation for 
harmony, spatial and musical. 111 Because this was such an all-encompassing world 
view, it did not willingly depart the philosophical stage. 

Neo-Platonism's loss of intellectual cache had a specific meaning and 
consequence for musical theory: from musical sound as number to vibration. 
Consonances were no longer based on simple numerical ratios but on vibration. The 
most concordant simultaneous tones were the ones whose vibrations coincided most 
frequently and regularly. Numbers were no longer the cause but only the 

119 

representation of what was happening musically. Vincenzo Galilei's exposure of 
the imperfections in Platonic intervals in the late sixteenth century was the leading 
edge of this dispassionate view of music informed by a mundane, knowable nature. 
Music in the modern world now is instrumental (both figuratively and literally), 

1 1 3 

efficient, and harmonically calculated. Equal temperament tuning is the ultimate 



Gozza, Number to Sound, 1. 
Gozza, Number to Sound, 2-4. 

Jamie Kassler, Inner Music: Hooke and North on Internal Character (Madison, Teaneck: Fairleigh 
Dickinson University Press, 1995), 53. 

Chua, "Vincenzo," in Clark and Rending, Music Theory, 20. 

46 



rationalization of music; tuning thus rationalized for the purpose of fretted 
instruments playing in harmony has lost magic and divinity 11 and implies a nature 
also thus diminished. Pre-modern music is highly rational in a literal sense — based on 
divine ratios — the "rational agent of enchantment." 1 ! Disenchantment of music 
means no less than the untuning of the cosmos, the collapse of cosmic order. 
Modernity views the disenchantment of musical theory and the rationalization of 
tuning as obvious and inevitable. 

But it was not so for seventeenth-century musical theorists or performers. The 
latter had been making novel tuning accommodations for instrumental and complex 
vocal music since the late Renaissance without confronting the philosophical 
contradiction with Pythagorean intervals. They simply did what they had to do to 
perform the music. This often meant mean-tone tempering: diminishing a series of 
consecutive fifth intervals by a bit; but it worked well for only a few keys. These 
ersatz temperament solutions were not systematized and only more or less 
satisfactory, usually limiting the keys that a performer could play in. "Just" 
intonation, Zarlino's system of using more intervals than in the Pythagorean 
philosophy, still had the inconvenient problem, because of using pure intervals, of 
music ending on a different pitch than the initial one: the basic problem of non- 
tempered tuning — the octave is not preserved. Dutch philosopher Huygens contended 
that good singers (unaccompanied) will compensate for this instability by holding the 
original pitch in their heads — in effect, creating their own tempered intervals. The 



Max Weber, The Rational and Social Foundations of Music. 
Chua, "Vincenzo Galilei/' in Clark and Rending, Music Theory, 22. 

47 



trick, apparently, according to Huygens, was to get them to sing a piece quickly 
enough so as not to forget the original pitch. 11 

Seventeenth-century theorists, in engaging more directly with the 
philosophical issues of music theory, typically accepted the necessity of some kind of 
temperament adjustment while still holding on to ideals of Pythagorean perfection. 
The logical and the ideal, then, co-existed through the century, the latter giving way 
to the former only as neo-Platonism and the idea of cosmological harmony lost 
intellectual space and became irrelevant, space then taken up by the new experimental 
philosophy. The co-existence of the pragmatic and the ideal was not always peaceful. 
Assumptions about nature informed musical treatises, which then became sites for 
contested notions of nature and the cosmos, though the authors would not have 
perceived them as such. 

Probably the most noted and prolific treatise writer of the early century, 
Thomas Morley's most important treatise on music theory was an instruction manual 
for singers and plucked instrument players on the intricacies of improvising two, 
three, four, five, six, or more parts on a plainsong melody. It is far from being an 
exact science. Modern music theory developed, haltingly and piecemeal, as a 
response to the increasing complexity of music beginning in the late Renaissance. 



116 Walker, Studies, 112. 



48 



Morley consults various sources "for a solution and a clearing of my doubt" for his 
own treatise and notes the "diursity betwixt them" 117 

Morley is not shy about proclaiming his own theory. He directs the reader to 
"dispose your musicke according to the nature of the words.... if you have a graue 
matter, applie a graue kinde of musicke to it. . . .when you would expresse any word 
signifying hardnesse. . .make the harmonie like vnto it, that is, somewhat harsh and 
hard but yet so it offend not. . . .sharpe thirds, sharpe sixes and such like." Going out 
of tune is unnatural because these are given by nature, not human artifice. 

Morley claims ancient sources for his musical writing, namely Plato for whom 
music was "a heauenly thing and profitable for the seeking out of that which is good 
and honest. . . .and cannot be intreated or taught without the knowledge of all other 
sciences." 11 Morley also cites Boethius (fifth-century Roman philosopher and 
mathematician whose five- volume De Musica informed music scholarship into the 
seventeenth century), who "did notwithstanding write more of musick than of al the 
other mathematical sciences" and "if it had not beene for him the knowledge of 

1 90 

musicke had not yet come into our Westerne part of the world." Morley cites these 
ancient sources to lend credibility to his own writing; but, despite his stridency about 
other musicians, he does not break any new ground about the philosophy of music, 



Thomas Morley, A plain and easie introduction to practical! musicke set downe in forme of a 
dialogue... .with many profitable rules to that effect (London: Peter Short, 1597), "To the Curteous 
Reader," page unnumbered. 

Morley, A plain and easie, part III, 177. 
119 Morley, A plain and easie, part III, 183-184. 

Morley, A plain and easie, part III, 184. 

49 



content to simply cite ancient sources without challenge even while suggesting 
pragmatic temperament practices. 

Everyone seems to have his (virtually never her) own composition and 
performance rules, and Morley claims to organize the chaos. He anticipates that many 
will read his book merely to find something for which to attack him by saying he is 
undercutting other practitioners with his own methods for making music; he 
proactively counter-attacks. "[T]his booke will be so farre from the hinderance of 
anie, that by the contrarie, it will cause those whome they alledge to be thereby 

191 

damnified, to be more able to giue reason for that which they do." — possibly an 
allusion to temperament practices, although he does not specify that. Anyone who 
thinks to have all the answers and condemns others is a fool, "imagining that all the 
guiftes of God should die in themselves, if they shoulde bee taken out of the 
worlde." 122 

The tension is almost palpable, even from the distance of 400 years; and the 
intensity of feeling seems a symptom of the challenging of closely held beliefs that 
underlay developing musical theory. Over the course of the century, the iron grip of 
these previously unquestioned beliefs about the nature of the cosmos as they impacted 
the practice of music loosened, not because anyone proclaimed it should be so but 
because a dogmatic adherence to Pythagorean perfectionism became inconvenient, an 
intellectual hanger-on. But early in the century, the intensity of feeling expressed in 
Morley' s treatise suggests a deep unease about the changing foundations of authority. 



Morley, "To the Courteous Reader/' in A plain and easie, page unnumbered. 
122 Morley, A plain and easie, Part II, 115. 

50 



Thomas Ravenscroft, in 1614, took on changes in practice and philosophy 
more directly. Music is being mightily abused in this "braine-sick Age wherein we 
hue,. . .neither Her selfe, nor her Lawes are regarded euen of her Children but 
most. . .runne after their owne rebellious Imaginations;" musicians pursue their own 
"priuate ends"... pretending to "Musicall Genius, and a religious disposition." These 
"Golden Sheepe, who are better Clad then Taught,. . .are willing to prostitute 
themselues to Dance after euery mans Pipe." He equates the discordant state of 
music with a commonweal which he sees in disarray. "Let Common Practice and her 
Complices censure me as they please,. . .1 ayme. . .to vindicate Her from these 
Salaecismes, and Barbarismes." He sees an ally in Morley, "who did shine in the 
Firmament of our Art, and did first giue light to our vnderstanding with his 
Praecepts" and who saw errors in the "Common Practice" but was "loath to break" 
with it — a pity, since, if he did, others would surely follow because of his 
influence. 

The upstart musicians of the "Common Practice" must be those who are 
taking on sacred nature, defying Pythagoras's divinely mandated precepts of music. 
"But I (says Ravenscroft) have search't the very Originall of our Art, and 
Etimologis. . .compar'd the Practise with the Theory, Nature with our Art. . .and I find 
it. . .extracted from the Quintessence of Arithmetick in the Rules and Praecepts.." 
Those of the Common Practice depart from the "Fundamental! Reasons of the 



Thomas Ravenscroft, A brief e discourse of the true (but neglected) use ofcharact'ring the degrees 
(London: Edward Alide, 1614), opening Apologie. 
Ravenscroft, discourse, Apologie. 

51 



1 9S 

Grounds and Rules of our Art." Following the first section of the Apologie, a series 
of noted musicians of the day vehemently proclaim the Tightness of Ravenscroft's 
stance. Ravenscroft then concludes the Apologie by saying that concord and discord 
exist in all the arts, not just music; and he views himself as a messenger of peace to 
the chaotic state of music, to bring it back into concord and harmony with nature. 

Both Ravenscroft and Morley, then, are almost pleading for a return to basics, 
to the ancients' wisdom about a cosmos based on perfect mathematical intervals and 
harmony, even though they had to use some kind of tempering to perform music. 
With their traditional stance, they are eschewing Bacon's roughly contemporaneous 
call to end speculation in music and just investigate it, as any other facet of nature; 
but there is no evidence that they either one knew or cared about Bacon's 
experimental advocacy. 

The first major theorist to accord with Bacon and to approach music 
experimentally rather than mystically was William Brouncker, future Royal Society 
president and translator, in 1653, of Descartes' 1618 Compendium musicae. 1 The 
introduction to the translation also included Brouncker' s own idea for dividing the 
scale with logarithms, the very anti-Pythagorean notion of dividing intervals into 
equal parts — the first one to propose this kind of manipulation. He wished to contest 
Descartes' claim that the consonances are based on arithmetic and show that their true 



Ravenscroft, discourse, Apologie. 

Still, Descartes relates in the Compendium that when drum skins of a wolf and a sheep are struck 
simultaneously, the sheepskin will remain silent for fear of the wolf. 

52 



1 97 

relationship is geometric. Interestingly, though, he did not seem at all interested in 
solving the tuning problem; in fact, his calculations for various ways of dividing 
intervals do not preserve the octave, the whole point of tempered tuning. Also in 
the introduction to the translation, Brouncker notes that the "complete musician" must 
have competence in the entire range of subjects touching on music, including 
mathematics and magic — and experimental science, especially acoustics: a 
Renaissance man and beyond! 

Coincidentally, in the same year that Brouncker translated Descartes' 
Compendium musicae, Hugh Piatt published The Jewel House of Art and Music and 
Nature. It was an essay in the new philosophy on a mission to subdue, tame, and 
correct nature, wildness, and exotica, 130 a popular and pragmatic sourcebook of 
human artifice to enhance nature. It was a distinct departure from Morley and 
Ravenscroft and heralded increasing intellectual space for the practical over the 
mystical. That space opened up even more at the end of the century as philosophers 
focused on mathematical solutions to temperament tuning and investigated 
consonances in the context of vibration science. 

Even in the last quarter of the century, though, Thomas Salmon tenaciously 
clung to the notion that the true consonances are those perfect ones given by 
Pythagoras. He unrelentingly campaigned for musicians' using just (untempered) 
intonation to duplicate the ethical effects of music that the ancients experienced. His 



Gouk, Music, Science, 142. 



128 Walker, Studies, 117. 

Gozza, Number to Sound, 20-21. 

Austern, "'Tis Nature's Voice/' in Clark and Rending, Music Theory, 40. 

53 



Essay to the Advancement ofMusick (1672) first argued his point passionately. In 
1688 he published A Proposal to Perform Mustek, in Perfect and Mathematical 
Proportions, in which he famously proposed complex mechanical appendages to 
instruments to compensate for the tuning discrepancy while maintaining just 
intonation; the system required interchangeable fingerboards and different frets for 
each string and was wildly impractical. He even gave up trying to explain the details 
and said that a mechanic would just have to figure it all out. 

In Chapter 1 of A Proposal, Salmon surveys the history of music. In ancient 
times, music had great power and flourished, then died during the "Darkness" of the 
medieval centuries. The present time is witness to a new glorious age of music with 
the potential of surpassing the ancients because of the advent of polyphony and many 
kinds of instruments. All are "beholding to the Excellent Genius of our Modern 
Musicians." Because of these advances, one might conclude, says Salmon, that 
nothing can be improved upon the present practice of music. 

But wait; there is something. The ancients made music with the "Accurate 
Observation of Proportions, which the Soul is from Heaven inform'd to Judge of, and 
the Body in Union with it, must Submit to." All the world agrees that the more exact 
the proportions, the more excellent the music; a singer or instrument out of tune will 
ruin the best composition. So it is a great error of the present day that the beauty of 
our music is "rendred Ineffectual, by tolerating so many unproportionate 



131 Walker, Studies, 115. 

Salmon, A Proposal To Perform Musick, In Perfect and Mathematical Proportions (London: John 
Lawrence, 1688), Chapter 1, 2. 

54 



1 ^^ 

imperfections." Since the octave must be stable, some kind of tempering is in 
order. Salmon goes on to technically detail the tuning problem on a "Viol," but then 
insists that the "Perfection" of ancient intervals must be used in the present day 
also. 134 

In Chapter 3, Salmon launches into the explanation of his solution for the 
tuning problem. "I have Calculated my Tables" to find the exact tuning discrepancy, 
and a "Mechanical Workman" then can fashion a "Finger-board" that the player 
simply adjusts for each key; but of course, each fret must be tuned separately. But he 
has tested it and found it to be very convenient! Salmon does not presume to tell the 
fashioner of the fingerboards how to do his job, as that artisan's expertise will suffice 
to find the best mechanical solution, possibly even better than the one Salmon himself 
has envisioned. 1 

Salmon admits that in a few instances, his system cannot correct the out-of- 
tuneness. "But this does not proceed from the defect of this Proposal, Nature it self 
will have it so." Then he seems to mitigate that statement a bit. "Scholars are not to 
alter Nature, but to discover her Constitutions, and to give opportunity for the best 
management of all her Intrigues." Still, he seems somewhat irked at nature for the 
imperfections in the supposedly perfect Pythagorean intervals but concludes by re- 
iterating that the proof is in the playing; his system indeed works. l Salmon straddles 
two epistemes: the ancients as the only true basis for music-making and the 



Salmon, Proposal, Chapter 1, 3-4. 
Salmon, Proposal, Chapter 2, 13. 
Salmon, Proposal, Chapter 3, 17-18. 
Salmon, Proposal, Chapter 3, 23-28. 



55 



recognition of ancient imperfection with a modern method to correct it. Like his 
contemporary Isaac Newton, Salmon identified with neo-Platonism; and Newton 
owned a copy of Salmon's A Proposal To Perform Mustek, In Perfect and 
Mathematical Proportions. 

Another major treatise writer at the end of the century, William Holder, 
manages to cite the ancients, offer pragmatic solutions for tuning, and add a religious 
devotional. He describes "Sound in General" in Chapter 1 and "Of Sound 
Harmonick" in Chapter 2, where he defines intervals in slavish detail, using both the 
monochord and pendulums to illustrate. In Chapter 3, "Of Consonance and 
Dissonance," consonances are determined by ratios of vibration pleasing to the ear, an 
aesthetic and natural rather than Pythagorean definition. In explaining the way 
vibrations work, Holder says that playing two notes that are separated by only a half- 
tone simultaneously causes "such a Battel in the Air between their disproportioned 

1 ^0 

Motions, sucha Clatter and Thumping, that it will be like the beating of a drum." 

Chapter 5, "Of Proportions," explains the complex system of logarithms to 
divide the scale in equal parts so to keep in tune, always keeping the diapason 
(octave) constant; the discrepancy between the perfect and tempered intervals, 
according to Holder, is approximately 1/53 of a diapason, which closely approximates 



William Holder, A Treatise of the Natural Grounds and Principles of Harmony (London: J. 
Heptinstall, 1694). 

The monochord was used in two ways: to explain perfect Pythagorean intervals and to explain 
ways of dividing the scale (or other intervals) into equal parts, usually as a solution to the tuning 
problem. 

Holder, Treatise, Chapter 3, 34. 

56 



the actual irrational number. 1 This logarithmic system for equal-temperament tuning 
is what Holder calls the "Natural Grounds of Harmony." 1 l He notes that Euclid "had 
a fair Hint. . .when he measured the Diapason by fix tones and found them to exceed 
the Interval of Diapason." But the ancients "did not pursue this Way of dividing the 
Systems." Holder is firm in saying, possibly for intuitive reasons, that only the 
approximations to the irrational numbers that precisely define the tuning discrepancy, 
not those "Irrational Contrivances[s]" themselves, should be used in creating equal- 
temperament tuning. In conclusion, he proposes some questions that bear further 
investigation: why do human voices at the same pitch sound so differently from one 
another? why do the sounds of the respective instruments differ so from each other? 
why do some people not love music? (He suggests an answer to this one; there is a 
"Falseness" in the auditory nerve that distorts the sound.) 1 Holder seems 
unquestioning about being in that epistemological space between neo-Platonism and 
experimental philosophy, and includes a heartfelt dedication and thanksgiving to God. 

Francis North, in 1677, wrote an extended and innovative essay on acoustics, 
dedicated to "A Friend" (possibly Hooke), noted in records of the Royal Society, and 
credited with being the beginning of modern music philosophy by at least one music 
historian. 1 By this time, acoustics and experimental investigation of sound were 



Holder, Treatise, Chapters, 67-84. 
Holder, Treatise, Chapter 6, 97. 

142 Holder, Treatise, Chapter 6, 116. 

143 Holder, Treatise, Chapter 9, 142. 

144 Holder, Treatise, Chapter 9, 152-153. 

Kassler, Jamie C, The Beginnings of the Modern Philosophy of Music in England: Francis North's 'A 
Philosophical Essay of Musick' (1677) with comments of Isaac Newton, Roger North and in the 
Philosophical Transactions (Hampshire, England and Burlington, Vermont: Ashgate, 2004). 

57 



coming to dominate music discussion, with a continuing pre-occupation with the 
criteria for concordant and discordant sound. Physical explanations were based on the 
coincidence theory of vibration. North accepted this, but ranks consonances in a 
different order than Hobbes and Galileo, for example, whose ranking was based on a 
Pythagorean arithmetical scheme; he ignores proportions in favor of sensory 
perception of synchronous pulses. 1 North was the first to investigate sound initiation 
and perception as well as the way the ear works as intermediary between these two 

1 4-7 

processes, a novel empirical approach. He suggests adding quarter tones to some 
notes as a way to preserve the octave and was the first to choose, from among the 

1 48 

twelve Greek modes, the two scales (major and minor) now in use. 

Still, an aura of moral judgment in discussions of tonality and concord lingers 
in North's essay: concordant sound is good, discordant sound is bad — a vestige of 
music's central place in the moral framework of the cosmos. Only pleasing harmony 
is acceptable as a desired musical sound; discord is allowable only on the way to a 
pleasing concord, when the ear is assured that it will be speedily resolved. 1 Music 
may also help the listener gain "ethical insights" because of its unique capability to 
express human affect. 



Kassler, Modern Philosophy, 52. 
Kassler, Modern Philosophy, 77. 
148 Kassler, Modern Philosophy, 79-81. 
Kassler, Modern Philosophy, 83. 
Kassler, Modern Philosophy, 87. 



58 



CHAPTER 5. THE NEW PHILOSOPHY: MUSIC AS SOURCE OF ORDER 

The waning of neo-Platonism, as well as Aristotelian natural philosophy, was 
in no way an indication of an increasing freedom from fear of disorder. Order anxiety 
was pervasive across classes and order widely perceived as fragile, a mere veneer 
sublimating anarchy. 1 2 From the first decades after 1500, all of Europe experienced a 
crisis of authority across all institutions and areas of human endeavor, including the 
arts, brought on by the Reformation and a range of other social and political 
changes. Thomas Hobbes' conviction that only the state prevented the war of each 
against each and that the problem of knowledge was the problem of order, led him to 
reject the experimental philosophy. Knowledge must not be tentative or contingent: 
absolute knowledge equaled social order. So for Hobbes, science must be premised 
on secure first causes, not in the business of investigating or debating them; and the 
failure of the new philosophy to proceed on a foundation of certain knowledge was no 
less than an invitation to civil war. 

Hobbes notwithstanding, the Civil War itself was not about abandoning order 
but rather overthrowing monarchial anarchy; and afterwards, society seemed 
collectively appalled at what had been wrought — regicide! — and willing to become 
acquiescing moderates at the Restoration. As old certainties about cosmological order 
and authority became increasingly tenuous in the wake of the century's religious and 



Kevin Sharpe and Peter Lake, eds., Culture and Politics in Early Stuart England (Palo Alto: Stanford 
University Press, 1993), 11. 

H. Floris Cohen, The Scientific Revolution: A Historiographical Inquiry (Chicago: University of 
Chicago Press, 1994), 210. 

Cohen, Scientific Revolution, 213-214. 



59 



political upheaval, an epistemological vacuum opened up; and the new philosophy, 
all about ruling and taming nature, filled that vacuum as a "hedge against 
disorder." 1 The order offered by the New Science was correcting, subduing, and 
classifying nature with human artifice. 

It was the right role at a critical time for the new philosophy. The century's 
chaos "interfere[d] drastically with the sense of mastery that knowledge confers." 1 
The sense of order was fundamentally shaken. This provided one impetus to put order 
into nature by "rationaliz[ing] strangeness and correcting] error." 1 Early in the 
century, Bacon had insisted that all errors in beliefs about nature should be banished. 
Thomas Browne answered the call to eliminate what he called "vulgar errors" in his 
Pseudodoxia Epidemica, in five re-issues, no less. Its organization is a metaphor for a 
newly ordered world he was trying to help create. It was a profound shift to this 
new source of order, one inevitably marked by ambivalence and befuddlement. Even 
as Browne repeatedly heaps scorn on both fundamentalist religious ideology and 
magical thinking, he unselfconsciously subscribes to the class prejudices of the time 
in condemning the lower classes for being unenlightened in the new philosophy; and 
his false dichotomy of the enlightened upper-class scientist versus the lower-class 
ignoramus fails to appreciate the fact of elites practicing alchemy, oblivious to its 
contradiction with the new philosophy, and laborers and artisans well- versed in 



Austern, "'Tis Nature's Voice/' in Clark and Rending, Music Theory, 40. 
Campbell, Wonder, 4. 
Campbell, Wonder, 6. 
Campbell, Wonder, 86. 

60 



1 SH 

understanding and absorbing the new ways of thinking about nature. Browne is just 
one who is reacting to loss of the old order by embracing the offer of a new one — 
dogmatically, in his case. 

Rising from the ashes of the Civil War at a time, not coincidentally, when 
England seemed anxious to leave all that disorder far behind, the conservative elites 
of the Royal Society appropriated the role of director of the new structure of order. At 
a time of unrest, sources of meaning and authority were eagerly grasped. l Science 
was promoted by the elites as a means of social control since it is everywhere the 
same, not volatile and complex like politics. One argument for the new philosophy 
was its "social utility" in maintaining order, a position articulated in Thomas Sprat's 
1667 History of the Royal Society. 160 This is not an argument for social reform but 
rather for benefiting elites in promoting the political and social status quo and 
stability — science for elites, not the wider population. Where Bacon had forcefully 
articulated science for social utility — for the material benefit of all — the elites 
repurposed the scientific endeavor, taking ownership of it as a force for social order 
and control. Identifying the New Science with social order, rather than subversive 
of it, propelled its acceptance; and for this reason, the break in order represented by 
the Civil War was the single most important event for the integration of the New 
Science. Moderate reformers morphed into social conservatives, the foundation for 



Campbell, Wonder, 97. 
Jardine, Ingenious Pursuits, 39. 

Margaret Jacob, The Cultural Meaning of the Scientific Revolution (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 
1988), 29-30. 

Jacob, Cultural Meaning, 38. 
Jacob, Cultural Meaning, 73. 

61 



the Royal Society. 163 Although the Society's strength waned toward the end of the 
century, the science it had promoted became the foundation of a new epistemology. 

The Society's method was to study nature through observation and 
experimentation; it was vehemently non-partisan, scorning and eschewing anything 
not purely "philosophical": 1 an ideal value-free space for scholarly pursuits. "A true 
history of nature, by purifying author's accounts of . . .partisan zeal" 1 was the goal, 
toward which results of observation and experiment could be marshaled. Philosophers 
wishing to join the Royal Society should be "laying aside all idle shadowy notions, 
[that] they may make a thorough examination of NATURE." 1 

The ideal, if totally unrealistic, principle of an ordered, value-free neutrality in 
the new philosophy was a powerful draw after the disastrous rivalries of the Civil 
War. In service of that end, several New Science philosophers wanted a language 
transparent to all, a new lingua franca of normative scientific discourse, stripped of all 
the richness, redundancy, and overtones of quotidian speech, signifying only and 
precisely the signified and reflecting a demystified nature. l 7 Wilkins developed the 
Wilkins Universal Language, used by Hooke to announce his balance spring watch 
mechanism. The universal language projects were dropped because of the 
impossible complexities involved. 1 Attempts to create a language somehow devoid 



Jacob, Cultural Meaning, 77-78. 

Dear, Revolutionizing the Sciences, 118. 

Henry Oldenburg (first secretary of Royal Society) in The Correspondence of Henry Oldenburg, eds. 
A. R. Hall and M. B. Hall (Madison and London: University of Wisconsin Press, 1966), letter 2445. 

Oldenburg, Correspondence, Letter 2372. 

Geneva, Astrology, 273. 

Jardine, Ingenious Pursuits, 317. 
169 Geneva, Astrology, 280-81. 

62 



of human content inevitably foundered on the same inherent impossibility as that of 
value-free science; but the belief of its possibility is evidence of the striving for 
defined order and authority in the wake of political rupture and philosophical 
dislocation. 

Acknowledging Diversity with Loss of Celestial Harmony 

As basic and long-held political, religious, and philosophical assumptions 
became fodder for re-examination, a necessary corollary was the necessity of 
acknowledging diversity. Although this sea change had been going on since before 
the dawn of the seventeenth century, the Civil War forced recognition of a new state 
of affairs. England, at Restoration, did not return to pre-war reality; the model of 
harmony and organic order could no longer be sustained. The religious and political 
conflict had come into glaring focus and could not be managed with a hegemonic 
ideal of unity and homogeneity. Tolerance for differing views, accommodation of 
diversity was the radically new challenge of the seventeenth century as it emerged 
into modernity. 

The first manifestation of the breakdown of unity, the Protestant Reformation, 
meant that sources of communal order shifted from public ritual and consensus to 
individual godliness; protestant spirituality was experienced individually rather than 
communally, symptomatic of the dismantling of the narrative of unity as a useful way 
to describe society. The fragmentation of religious belief presaged and hastened 



Keith Thomas, "Women and the Civil War Sects/' in Crisis in Europe 1560-1660, ed. Trevor Aston, 
(New York: Basic Books, Inc., 1963), 335. 

63 



accommodation of political and philosophical fragmentation. In this way, the 
Protestant Reformation acted as a "midwife for the future," 171 a future defined by 
secularism of the modern state in Western society. 

The abandonment of unity was centered in the tumult within natural 
philosophy. Much more than merely the seventeenth-century term for science, natural 
philosophy was a more comprehensive belief system about cosmological structure 
and meaning, the character of matter and of cause, and the proper basis for natural 
knowledge — not conformable to any single modern discipline. Competing claims of 
Aristotelian-based Scholasticism, neo-Platonism, and the new mechanical philosophy 
characterize the entire seventeenth century; and interpreting the changes as a simple 
case of natural philosophy sinking into oblivion as science brilliantly ascends is a 
profoundly misreading of the cultural significance of all of the voices in the 
conversation of the seventeenth century. The competing sources of authority, the 
fragmentation itself, are the story of budding modernity. 

In music, the waning of the ideal of unity meant the abandonment of the 
absolute: intervals are not quite perfect and consonance is not an absolute quality, but 
one of degree. Rather than based on perfect Pythagorean intervals, consonance came 
to be recognized as the coincidences of the termination of frequency cycles between 
two strings. Frequency ratios are not placed into discrete categories of consonance or 



Patrick Collinson, The Birthpangs of Protestant England: Religious and Cultural Change in the 
Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries, (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1988), 59. 
Anstey and Schuster, Science of Nature, 1-2. 

64 



non-consonance, but rather are on a continuum of consonance. So the idea of 
concord changed from mystical numbers as the foundation to coincidence of sound 
vibration. The most concordant simultaneous tones are ones that coincide most 
regularly and frequently; infrequent or random tones are discordant. Numbers are no 
longer the cause, but merely the representation of sound. Concord and discord are not 
contradictory qualities but part of a continuum. 17 This abandonment of the absolute 
quality of consonance is both manifestation of and metaphor for the changes wrought 
in seventeenth-century natural philosophy. 

Continuing Religiosity With Philosophical Changes 

The single characteristic shared among virtually all writers, philosophers, and 
theorists alike is a profound religiosity. From the religious foundation of Bacon's 
agenda for the new philosophy to better the lot of humankind to Newton's 
preoccupation with ancient religious revelation, this century was marked by the 
primacy of religion. Even as the seeds of fragmentation, diversity, and thus 
secularism were sown by the Protestant Reformation, individual writers consistently 
and clearly articulated their religious commitments. This remains true even as ideas 
of nature and the cosmos, of order and authority, were being renegotiated, as seen in 
the musical treatises. 



Claude V. Palisca, "Scientific Empiricism in Musical Thought/' in Seventeenth-Century Science and 
the Arts, ed. Hedley Howell Rhys (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1961), 109. 
Kassler, Inner Music, 53. 

65 



Still, this renegotiation in areas touching on religion created a cloud of 
suspicion of atheism over the new philosophy. The College of Physicians, feeling 
their status quo threatened by the new philosophy, hired an agitator to attack scientists 
of the Royal Society as being anti-religious and so undermining the social order and 
the common understanding of God. Accusations of irreligiosity, albeit by a paid 
rabble-rouser, could be taken seriously. The crux of the attack was that the 
mechanical God of the new philosophers is not omnipotent and so can no longer work 
miracles. 175 

Suspicion about the new philosophy was not limited to the uninformed. After 
the Restoration, when the conservative elite dominated and busily institutionalized 
the new science, Leibniz scorned the new philosophers' seemingly contradictory 
claims for a clockmaker God Who created the cosmos and stepped away to let it run 
according to physical laws on one hand, while yet being interested in the minutiae of 
human existence on the other. 17 Some historians since have also read the new 
philosophers' religious protestations as somehow disingenuous, cynically crafted to 

1 77 

appease a doubting public. This reading, though, belies a historicist understanding 
of this very religious century; and part of the answer for the conundrum of 
continuing, sincere religious belief among the new philosophers rests on two notions 
of God uneasily co-existing through Church history and brought into relief in this 
century of upheaval. 



Francis Oakley, Omnipotence, Covenant, and Order (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1984). 
His scorn was particularly directed at Newton and became intertwined with their bitter rivalry over 
which of the two was the first inventor of the calculus. 
Oakley, Omnipotence, 73. 

66 



The two notions of God refer to the dual powers of God, absolute and 
ordinary, vying for primacy through the Middle Ages, Renaissance, and into the 
seventeenth century. God's absolute powers are philosophically aligned with 
Platonism, which inhered in early Christian theology, and are associated with the 
Great Chain of Being; God is not constrained by anything and is able and free to even 
suspend physical laws, as in the working of miracles. By contrast, God's ordinary 
powers are philosophically aligned with Aristotle and became the dominant notion of 
God with the influx of his (Aristotle's, not God's) writings in the twelfth century. 
God's ordinary powers are those of the God Who created a lawful cosmos and 
adheres to those laws; as such, He is knowable and transparent to rational 
investigation. Scholasticism, which enshrined this latter notion of God, dominated 
Church teaching well into the seventeenth century, notwithstanding an attack by 
fourteenth-century nominalists who maintained that God is inscrutable and not 
amenable to rationalist analysis — philosophical adumbration of the seventeenth- 

1 7Q 

century scientific revolution. 

The elite, post-Restoration new philosophers of the seventeenth century, then, 
tapped into both notions of God, the dual powers of God, in claiming both a Creator 
God of a lawful cosmos as well as a personal, unconstrained God Who could 
transcend these laws if he wished (which He has promised by covenant not to do). 
This was their stance against charges of atheism, a more embracing, not limiting, 



The famous condemnation of Aristotle by the Bishop of Paris in 1277 was an attack on the 
Aristotelian idea that God could in any way be constrained, including by divinely created physical 
laws. The Bishop lost that battle. 

Oakley, Omnipotence, 81. 

67 



notion of God. Understanding these religious subtleties undermines the theologically 
uninformed interpretation of seventeenth-century protestations of religiosity as either 
naivete or deliberate obfuscation. One cannot know the minds of individuals, of 
course; but certainly the prevailing sentiment of the century was one of sincere 
religiosity. 

The religiosity permeated all of society and was not limited to some narrow 
philosophical — religious agenda of the elites. Musical treatise writers credited 
religious motivation and inspiration for their efforts or simply alluded to God in 
incidental ways throughout their treatises. In his 1588 treatise on vocal and 
instrumental music, John Case declares that music has "God for a father and nature 
for a mother." " The character of these allusions subtly shifted, not surprisingly, 
through the century. Early on, references to the Divine actually embraced God, the 
cosmos, and heavenly harmony. Late in the century, religion became disengaged from 
natural philosophy as the new, morally neutral experimental science moved into 
philosophy's intellectual space; and Godly references are deliberate rather than 
incidental, forceful re-articulations of that which seems threatened because no longer 
philosophically necessary. 

Religion, though still vitally important to individuals, necessarily engaged 
differently with an emerging philosophy that was not dependent on moral meaning in 



Earlier in the century, before the conservative, moderate elites dominated the New Science and 
institutionalized it with the establishment of the Royal Society, radical Protestant reformers and new 
scientists had formed a pragmatic alliance, united primarily in their opposition to the Roman Church, 
though for different reasons. Puritan theological rigidity caused the breakdown of this tenuous 
alliance well before the Restoration. 

John Case, quoted in Austern, "'Tis Nature's Voice," in Clark and Rheding, Music Theory, 30. 

68 



the universe; and this is apparent in music treatises. In his 1694 musical treatise 
scientifically analyzing the division of the scale, William Holder still proclaims the 
divine in music. Following a detailed discussion of intervals and tuning, Holden goes 
on to state that God's wisdom and goodness order the "Nature of Harmony" and are 
more than we can hope to fully understand, although the search for answers must go 
on. Music is an essential part of worship and should be used "for our great Creator's 

1 89 

Praise, as He is the Founder and Donor of it." Toward the end of the century, St. 
Cecelia morphed into the patron saint of music, not her original role, as she became 

1 8^ 

identified with nature's female embodiment of music (Musica). As nature lost its 
cosmological significance, it became increasingly identified with religion. This 
natural theology was in ascendance, compatible with the new experimental 
philosophy. 

Thomas Mace and Nicholas Brady both wrote, during the last quarter of the 
seventeenth century, about the importance of music in praising God. Each treatise has 
an anxiously persuasive tone, as if needing to justify its stance. Mace, a cleric at 
Cambridge University, created a widely used and respected instructional manual for 
singing correctly and in tune in church, so as to glorify God. Interestingly, he 

I 84 

dedicates it especially to the "Discenting Ministry," who might not be initially 
friendly to the idea of music in church; Mace is on a mission to convince them 



182 Holder, Treatise, 54-55. 

Austern, "'Tis Nature's Voice/' in Clark and Rheding, Music Theory, 59. 

Thomas Mace, Musick's Monument, or A Rembrancer of the best practical musick, both divine and 
civil, that has ever been known to have been in the world (London: T. Ratcliffe and N. Thompson, 
1676), frontispiece. 

69 



otherwise. The first part instructs congregations of parochial churches how to sing 
psalms well, or do not bother to sing them at all, and suggests how cathedral music 

IOC 

may be "much improved." 

In rhyming verse, Mace insists that clerics must lead by example, learning 
music well to set a high musical standard as a model for their congregations. 
"Example is The Thing:/ Ther's but One Way, which is, Your Selves to Sing." It is 
better to not sing at all than to sing badly. "Admonishing your selves, (in Sweet 
Acchord)/ In Singing Psalms, with Grace unto the Lord./ Sed sine Arte, That cannot 
be done,/ Et sine Arte, Better let alone." Ancient King David, psalm singer and 
harp player, is the shining example of musical leadership, out in the world rather than 
cloistered with books, able even to fashion his own musical instruments. "How can 
He [cleric] be a Judge of Good, or 111,/ When (in That Thing) Defective's He of 
Skill?" 

Mace acknowledges he is speaking boldly, but knows that advocating for 
music in church is "True Doctrine." Departing from rhyme now, Mace says he may 
be taking a position "against the General Swing of the Times," but cares not about 
offending those who reject his advocacy of excellent church music, the "Sleight and 
Trivial," people. Music is divinely mysterious, as will be obvious to anyone who 
earnestly studies it, capable of stirring great religious ecstasy. Mace goes on to vilify, 
with much name-calling, those who criticize his argument from a stance of ignorance 



Mace, Mustek's, frontispiece. 

Mace, Mustek's, first part, page unnumbered. 

Mace, Mustek's, first part, page unnumbered. 



70 



of music. "Let Things Alone, you do not Vnderstand." He considers it a pity that so 
few understand the "wonderful-powerful-efficacious Virtues" music "has upon the 
Souls and Spirits of Men Divinely-bent." 

Music sung in tune is a "simile of God," while "Jarring Discords are. . .a simile 
of the Devil." Music is to raise souls to God, enhancing the worship experience. Mace 
feels impelled to provide instruction in good singing to parochial churches to 
counteract the shocking state of musicianship among non-cathedral congregations. 
Very interestingly, he claims that singing in tune unaccompanied is a virtual 
impossibility, even for a singer with a discerning ear; instrumental accompaniment is 
required to keep both a solo singer and an entire congregation in tune. So nature's gift 
of music must be enhanced by human artifice; and the organ is the best choice. Even 
an indifferent singer would be hard-pressed to sing out of tune with an organ guiding 
the musical way. 190 And Mace offers proof, real proof, of the efficacy of tuneful 
singing, a "thing most eminently remarkable." During a 1644 siege by three armies at 
York Cathedral, which was filled with people, the cannon shot was unable to 
penetrate the walls and all inside were kept safe because of the congregation's 
angelic, tuneful psalm-singing. 1 2 

In his discussion of cathedral music, following the parochial music section, 
Mace attacks more directly the dissenters who eschew music in church. He says that 
England has attained the highest level of art in church music composition; and to 



Mace, Mustek's, first part, page unnumbered. 
Mace, Mustek's, Chap. II, page unnumbered. 

190 Mace, Mustek's, Chap. V, 9. 

191 Mace, Mustek's, Chap. V, 19-20. 



71 



refuse to use this divine resource for worship is to profane it. He then offers a prayer 
that God will bring into "Concord and Perfect Unity All Dissenting, Jarring, and 
Discording Christians, so that they may have a Right Discerning of the True Worship 
and Service of Him." Only then, in imitation of heavenly choirs, will worship be 
acceptable to God. But Mace has only begun his diatribe against music-eschewing 
dissenters. Beginning with "Kind Ignoramus," he proceeds with a most vicious- 
sounding castigation of those who would deny in worship that which "Angels Love, 
and Devils Abhor. . .which clearly differ [entiate]s Heav'n from Hell." Apparently, 
the bitterness of the banning of church music during the interregnum is little abated at 
this point. The dissension and disunity for which there is not yet a political language 
are yet capable of being expressed in art. 

The bulk of the treatise, nearly 250 pages, instructs singers and 
instrumentalists in the fine art of making tuneful music for the purpose of right 
worship. Mace concludes with a general discussion about concord and discord that 
almost reads as if written in the first part of the century because it emphasizes the 
mystical character of music, something far more than the sum of the musical parts. He 
reverts to the old standby of the stretched string to begin an explanation of intervals, 
but, curiously, confines himself to explanation of the octave, repeatedly created by 
halving a string's sounding length any number of times. (Perhaps Mace thought that 
any complicated discussion of the tuning problem would distract from his core 
message.) Music is characterized by "Contra-Qualities" — love and hate, light and 



192 Mace, Mustek's, Ch. V, 29. 



193 Mace, Mustek's, "An EPISTLE To all Ignorant Despisers OF THIS Divine Part of MUSICK," 30. 

72 



dark, good and evil — "Perceived by the Conchords, and Dischords: Agreements, and 
Disagreements, betwixt the 7 Distinct Tones." 1 Music carries moral weight. But 
Mace also demonstrates a more modern approach in moving beyond intervals to focus 
on chords as well, especially the 1-3-5 chord, particularly harmonic because 
reflecting the Holy Trinity. The concordance of three voices singing the tones 
simultaneously is much more pleasing than hearing them sounded separately, the 
reason for which is "an occult mystery." 

Mace concludes by re-iterating than anyone who tries out his system of 
learning to make good music will, in the process, discover music's mystical and 
divine wonders and "shall never after Degenerate into That Gross Sub-Beastical Sin 
of Atheism." 196 He cannot resist a short adjunct section about the mystical power of 
music, "there being Nothing of Art, and Science, under Heaven, more Properly 
Significantly, and Powerfully fit for Divine, and Contemplative Good Christians, than 

1 Q7 

It." Because of its spiritual and emotional power, music should not be used to "stir 
up, and Excite Lightness, Vainness, Jocundity, and Folly," but used only to serve 

1 Q8 

God. It is "That Eternal, and Coelestial Language." Music retains mystical power; 
but it is located squarely within the divine religious experience, with no connection to 
neo-Platonic mysticism or Pythagorean perfect intervals. Even in his discussion of the 
stretched string to explain the wonder of the octave, Mace avoids any mention of 



194 Mace, Mustek's, 265. 

195 Mace, Mustek's, 267. 

196 Mace, Mustek's, 268. 

197 Mace, Mustek's, 270. 

198 Mace, Mustek's, 272. 



73 



these ancient sources, focusing exclusively on the religious foundation of music's 
spiritual power. 

Even later in the century, Nicholas Brady — cleric and librettist for Henry 
Purcell — preached a notable sermon evoking some of Mace's themes. 1 Brady 
begins by cataloging events in the Bible celebrated by heavenly music, seeming to 
belabor the point as he cites Bible verses focusing on the centrality of music on 
numerous spiritually notable occasions. He concludes from this that music, both 
vocal and instrumental, is used and approved of by God. "[T]he proper Office of 
Musick in the Service of God, is to praise him, and. . .we may observe in the last 
place, how Signal an evidence God has been pleased to give of his avow'd allowance 

901 

and approbation" of music. 

Religion, according to Brady, is the "most entertaining thing in 
Nature. . .encouraging the truest chearfulness, and not. . .condemning any Innocent 
Delights." Those who would have religion consist of only "Moroseness and 
Austerity" by banning music from worship have done religion a great disservice; and 
it would be unnecessary to make that obvious point if it were not for "a party of Men" 

909 

who unaccountably find music in church "extremely culpable." God Himself 
enjoins man to make music; and the fact that the "Heavenly Art" is corrupted by 
some is no reason to eschew it altogether. If that argument for its banning from 



Nicholas Brady, Church-musick vindicated: a sermon preach'd at St. Bride's church, on Monday, 
November 22, 1697, being St. Caecilia's day, the anniversary feast of the Lovers of music (London: 
Printed for Joseph Wilde, 1697). 

Brady, Church-musick, 2-5. 

Brady, Church-musick, 5-6. 

Brady, Church-musick. 8. 

74 



religious use were reasonable, it would follow that poetry should also be banned from 
religious use because of the debauchery of some verses. Music naturally directs us to 
"Mansions of Joy" having in it "something of Divinity. . .which acts upon the Soul 
with such a sweet Violence." Alluding to recent political discord, a shattering of 
the peace now mended, Brady offers a prayer that all the "several parties in the 
kingdom, however formerly divided by interest or design, would. . .resemble the 
Trumpeters and Singers in the Text [Bible] . . .and [be] as one. . .in Praising and 
Thanking the Lord!" ( Brady concludes by saying he is sorry for those "whose 
unhappy Aversion to Divine Harmony, renders them unlike to the Saints and Blessed 
Spirits" who join with God in making heavenly music. 

Like Mace, Brady makes mention of neither Plato nor Pythagoras in his 
urgent advocacy of instrumental and vocal music in church. He speaks lovingly and 
passionately about the mystical and divine properties of music, capable of moving 
men to heights of joy and wonder, eliciting from them the best that God has put into 
humanity. None of this has to do with ancient wisdom, though; it is all about the 
Christian religious experience. The divinity of music is not to be found in number 
mysticism but in its power to connect humans to the divine presence through this 
divinely ordained art. 



Brady, Church-musick, 10-12. 
Brady, Church-musick, 17. 
Brady, Church-musick, 23. 



75 



CHAPTER 6. CONCLUSION 

Music writing offers a window to illuminate the changes wrought over the 
course of the tumultuous seventeenth century concerning sources of order and 
authority. The fragmentation across political and religious institutions was mirrored 
in profound changes in natural philosophy. As the narrative of the harmony of the 
spheres lost intellectual space to New Science, treatises and other music writing 
became sites for contested ideas about shifting intellectual spaces. 

Religion seems to be a constant; writers throughout the century express deep 
and sincere religious sentiments which are not apparently diminished by the new 
natural philosophy or the fragmentation in religion itself. The constancy is an illusion, 
though. Even if individual sentiment did not wane, the way in which religion engaged 
with philosophy changed fundamentally. When the harmony of the spheres was 
dominant, a unified vision of the cosmos with a place for everything (and everyone) 
and everything in its place, religion was part of that unified scheme; it shared 
cosmological space with natural philosophy. But as ideas of nature drastically 
changed and the new experimental philosophy came into ascendance, there was no 
longer any intellectual space for religion. Religion became extraneous: a personal 
choice rather than a philosophical necessity. The urgent-sounding re-articulation of 
the importance of church music after the Restoration attests to a growing, if still 
unconscious, nervousness about the cultural role for religion when it no longer 
mattered to the new philosophy. 



76 



When the cosmos was tuned to the music of the spheres, order inhered 
throughout the universe, a given of human existence. But when the cosmic music was 
silenced, order was no longer to be found in the cosmos. Humankind was now 
unencumbered, free from cosmic control and the certainly that accompanied it. Order 
must now be imposed by a newly autonomous humankind. Music treatises illuminate 
that highly contested process, fraught as it was with such great cosmological 
significance, revealing a deep level of discomfort as previously unquestioned 
certainties are now fodder for debate. The level of vitriol is astounding as debates 
were fought bitterly over issues ranging from the inconsequential — whether or not to 
label notes with syllable names — to the central problem of the Platonic foundation of 
intervals. The bitterness and deep animosity among treatise writers seems to encode 
the fear of the new reality of a desacralized cosmos. 

The tuning problem, that the Platonic intervals were not perfect at all for 
performing polyphonic and instrumental music — along with the corollary issues of 
the nature of consonance and the proper division of the scale — was the most critical 
issue for the music world in the seventeenth century and was met by a variety of 
responses that shed light on the way epistemological change occurred over the course 
of the seventeenth century. 

The tuning problem could not reasonably be ignored; musical performance 
demanded some kind of resolution. For some, it was the elephant in the room. They 
worked around it — limiting the music they played or the range of music, limiting the 
keys they used to perform music, making on-the-spot adjustments to instruments or 

77 



individual tuning of instruments for specific pieces — but not confronting, 
metaphysically or technologically, the core issue of the imperfection of the Platonic 
intervals. 

Of the other perhaps more philosophically-inclined thinkers and writers on 
music, some may have been excited about the new experimental philosophy and not 
sorry to give up cosmological certainty for the prize of new knowledge of nature and 
a tuning "cure" for the inconveniently inadequate Platonic intervals. Bacon, though 
not offering comment about tuning specifically, forcefully eschewed musical 
mysticism. Hooke seemed unabashed by the metaphysical consequences of tempered 
tuning, eagerly joining in the search for the most useful solution. Newton's entire 
sense of reality was founded on Platonic mysticism, but he also joined in the musical 
discussion of new kinds of tuning, commenting on Francis North's essay on 
acoustics, consonance, and the scale. 

Most of the both philosophically- and musically-inclined were more mixed in 
their confrontations with the tuning issue. They developed or subscribed to new 
tuning paradigms while convincing themselves that, somehow, Platonic certainty still 
inhered in the cosmos. This was Thomas Salmon, who invented ludicrously unwieldy 
mechanical contraptions to fit on instruments so that musicians could still use just 
intonation. Others saw various methods of dividing the scale into equal pieces to 
develop a system of tempered tuning not as abandoning but rather redefining cosmic 
harmony. The range of responses is witness to the shifting and re-alignment of 
intellectual space in the seventeenth century. 

78 



Because of this metaphysical and intellectual jostling, neo-Platonism and the 
harmony of the spheres, cosmological certainty and a unified narrative of religious, 
political, and cultural reality all were eventually squeezed out of meaningful 
existence. But it was not because anyone made it so; and it was not deliberate, 
systematic, or linear. Certainly there was never a conference called to discuss the 
tuning problem and come up with a workable solution or fashion a compromise. Even 
the kind of profound epistemological change such as occurred in the seventeenth 
century is piecemeal, unconscious, at times retrograde. There is no zero-sum game of 
experimental philosophy or tempered tuning advancing and taking over the old 
cosmological thinking. Music lost cosmological significance, not through willful 
advocacy, but because it ceased to be an important way to view the cosmos. 

No one in the seventeenth century, even the brightest and most prescient, 
could have surveyed the sweep of the century and announced the epistemological 
shift. There is no announcer, neither declarer nor decider. The paradox of historical 
change is that it occurs only through sentient, willful actors; yet what is wrought is 
unforeseen, little understood, and largely unintended, always prey to some level of 
historical contingency, and written in the passive voice. People through the century 
placed a host of meanings on the political, religious, and philosophical upheaval; and 
change happened, fundamentally and permanently. 



79 



WORKS CITED 



Anstey, Peter B. and John A. Schuster. The Science of Nature in the Seventeenth 
Century: Patterns of Change in Early Modern Natural Philosophy . New 
York: Springer, 2005. 

Anstey, Peter B. "Experimental Versus Speculative Natural Philosophy." In Anstey 
and Schuster, eds. 

Aston, T. H. Crisis in Europe, 1560-1660. New York: Basic Books, 1965. 

Austern, Linda Phyllis. '"Tis Nature's Voice: music, natural philosophy and the 

hidden world in seventeenth-century England." In Music Theory and Natural 
Order from the Renaissance to the Early Twentieth Century, edited by 
Suzannah Clark and Alexander Rehding. New York: Cambridge University 
Press, 2001. 

Aveni, Anthony F. Behind the Crystal Ball: Magic, Science, and the Occult From 
Antiquity Through the New Age. New York: Times Books, 1996. 

Bacon, Francis, and Richard Foster Jones. Essays, Advancement of Learning, New 
Atlantis and Other Pieces. New York: Odyssey Press, 1937. 

Barnes, Barry, and Steven Shapin. Natural Order: Historical Studies of Scientific 
Culture. Thousand Oaks: SAGE Publications, 1979. 

Brady, Nicholas. Church-musick vindicated a sermon preach 'd at St. Bride's church, 
on Monday, November 22, 1697, being St. Caecilia's day, the anniversary 
feast of the Lovers ofmusick. London: Printed for Joseph Wilde, 1697. 

Campbell, Mary B.. Wonder and Science: Imagining Worlds in Early Modern 
Europe. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1999. 

Chua, Daniel. "Vincenzo Galilei, modernity, and the division of nature." In Music 
Theory, eds. Clark and Rehding. 

Clark, Suzannah, and Alexander Rehding. Music Theory and Natural Order from the 
Renaissance to the Early Twentieth Century. New York: Cambridge 
University Press, 2001. 

Cohen, H. Floris. The Scientific Revolution: A Historio graphical Inquiry. Chicago: 
University of Chicago Press, 1994. 

Collinson, Patrick. The Birthpangs of Protestant England: Religious and Cultural 
Change in the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries. New York: Macmillan, 

80 



1988. 

Dear, Peter. Revolutionizing the Sciences: European Knowledge and Its Ambitions, 
1500-1700. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001. 

Dolnick, Edward. The Clockwork Universe: Isaac Newton, the Royal Society, and the 
Birth of the Modern World. New York: HarperCollins, 2011. 

Farrington, Benjamin and Francis Bacon. The Philosophy of Francis Bacon; An 
Essay on Its Development From 1603 to 1609. Liverpool: Liverpool 
University Press, 1964. 

Geneva, Ann. Astrology and the Seventeenth Century Mind: William Lilly and the 
Language of the Stars. Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1995. 

Godwin, Joscelyn. Music, Mysticism, and Magic: A Sourcebook. London: Routledge 
& Kegan Paul, 1986. 

Gouk, Penelope. Music, Science, and Natural Magic in Seventeenth-Century 
England. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1999. 

Gozza, Paolo. Number to Sound: The Musical Way to the Scientific Revolution. New 
York: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2000. 

Hellyer, Marcus. The Scientific Revolution: The Essential Readings. USA: Blackwell 
Pub., 2003. 

Herissone, Rebecca. Music Theory in Seventeenth-Century England. London: Oxford 
University Press, 2000. 

Holder, William. Treatise of the natural grounds and principals of harmony: a 
facsimile of the 1694 London edition. New York: Broude Bros., 1967. 

Jacob, Margaret C. The Cultural Meaning of the Scientific Revolution. Philadelphia: 
Temple University Press, 1988. 

James, Jamie. The Music of the Spheres: Music, Science, and the Natural Order of the 
Universe. New York City: Copernicus Press, 1995. 

Jardine, Lisa. Ingenious Pursuits: Building the Scientific Revolution. New York: Nan 
A. Talese (Doubleday, Random House), 1999. 

Kassler, Jamie Croy. Inner Music: Hobbes, Hooke, and North on Internal Character. 
Madison, N.J.: Fairleigh Dickinson University Press, 1995. 

Kassler, Jamie Croy, and Francis North Guilford. The Beginnings of the Modern 

81 



Philosophy of Music in England: Francis North's "A philosophical essay of 
musick" (1677) with Comments of Isaac Newton, Roger North and in the 
Philosophical Transactions. Oxford: Ashgate, 2004. 

Mace, Thomas. Musick 's monument. New York: Broude, 1966. 

McGrath, Alister E.. In the Beginning: The Story of the King James Bible and How It 
Changed a Nation, a Language, and a Culture. New York: Doubleday, 2001. 

Morley, Thomas. A plain and easy introduction to practical music. New York: 
Norton, 1953. 

Oakley, Francis. Omnipotence, Covenant & Order: An Excursion in the History of 
Ideas from Abelard to Leibniz. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1984. 

Oldenburg, Henry. The Correspondence of Henry Oldenburg. Madison: University of 
Wisconsin Press, 1975. 

Palisca, Claude V. "Scientific Empiricism in Musical Thought." In Seventeenth- 
Century Science and the Arts, edited by Hedley Howell Rhys. Princeton, NJ: 
Princeton University Press, 1961. 

Porter, Roy. "Creation and Credence: The Careers of Theories of the Earth in Britain, 
1600-1820." In Natural Order, Barnes and Shapin, eds. 

Price, Bronwen. Francis Bacon's The New Atlantis: New Interdisciplinary Essays. 
Manchester and New York: Manchester University Press, 2002. 

Ravenscroft, Thomas. A brief discourse: 1614. Repr. ed. Kilkenny: Boethius Press, 
1984. 

Rhys, Hedley Howell and Stephen Toulmin. Seventeenth-Century Science and the 
Arts. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univ. Press, 1961. 

Rossi, Paolo. Francis Bacon: From Magic to Science. Chicago: University Of 
Chicago Press, 1968. 

Russell, Conrad. The Origins of the English Civil War. New York: Barnes & Noble 
Books, 1973. 

Sacks, Oliver W.. The Man Who Mistook his Wife for a Hat and Other Clinical Tales. 
New York: Summit Books, 1985. 

Sacks, Oliver W.. Musicophilia: Tales of Music and the Brain. New York: Alfred A. 
Knopf, 2007. 



82 



Salmon, Thomas, and John Wallis. A proposal to perform musick in perfect and 

mathematical proportions containing I. the state of musick in general, II. the 
principles of present practice ..., III. the tables of proportions, calculated for 
the viol .... London: Printed for John Lawrence ..., 1688. 

Schafer, R. Murray. The Tuning of the World. New York: Random House Inc.: A. A. 
Knopf, 1977. 

Schuster, John Andrew, and Peter R. Anstey. The Science of Nature in the 
Seventeenth Century: Patterns of Change in Early Modern Natural 
Philosophy. New York: Springer, 2005. 

Serjeantson, Richard. "Natural knowledge in The New Atlantis.'''' In Francis Bacon 's 
New Atlantis, ed. Price. 

Shapin, Steven. The Scientific Revolution. Chicago: University Of Chicago Press, 
1996. 

Sharpe, Kevin. Remapping Early Modern England: The Culture of Seventeenth- 
Century England. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000. 

Sharpe, Kevin and Peter Lake, eds. Culture and Politics in Early Stuart England. 
Palo Alto: Stanford University Press, 1993. 

Sobel, Dava. Longitude: The True Story of a Lone Genius Who Solved the Greatest 
Scientific Problem of His Time. New York: Walker, 1995. 

Spedding, James, Robert Leslie Ellis, and Douglas Dennon Heath. The Works of 
Francis Bacon. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1904. 

Thomas, Keith. Man and the Natural World: Changing Attitudes in England, 1500- 
1800. London: Oxford University Press, 1996. 

Thomas, Keith. "Women in the Civil War Sects." In Crisis in Europe 1560-1660, 
edited by Trevor Ashton. New York: Basic Books, Inc., 1963. 

Walker, D.P.. Studies in Musical Science in the Late Renaissance. London: Warburg 
Institute, University of London, 1978. 

Weber, Max, Don Martindale, Gertrud Neuwirth, and Johannes Riedel. The Rational 
and Social Foundations of Music. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University 
Press, 1958. 

Webster, Charles. From Paracelsus to Newton: Magic and the Making of Modern 
Science. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1982. 



83 



Weinberger, Jerry. "On the Miracles in Bacon's New Atlantis." In Price, ed. 



84